Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-669899f699-8p65j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-05-02T03:03:32.918Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter 6 - Perception as a Discriminative Activity

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 May 2025

Robert Roreitner
Affiliation:
Charles University, Prague

Summary

The chapter provides a novel account of perceptual discrimination (krinein) in Aristotle. Against the widespread view that the most basic perceptual acts consist in noticing differences between two or more perceived qualities, I argue that discrimination is for Aristotle more like sifting, winnowing on a sieve: it consists in identifying – with an ultimate authority – the quality of an external object as distinct from any other quality of the given range that the object could have. The chapter further explores how the notion of discrimination is embedded by Aristotle within his causal assimilation model of perception. I argue that the central notion of a discriminative mean (mesotēs), introduced in An. 2.11, is intended to capture the role of the perceptive soul as the controlling factor of a homeostatic mechanism underlying perception. As such the notion lays the groundwork for resolving the apparent conflict between the passivity of perception and the impassivity of the soul (as analysed in Chapter 5). The prospect is further explored in Chapter 7. The present chapter concludes by arguing that Aristotle conceives perceptual discrimination as a holistic assessment of the external object acting on the perceiver, including those of its features which are not causally efficacious.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2025
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NC
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

6.1 The Logic of Discrimination

We have seen (in Section 4.7) that Aristotle’s notion of perceptual discrimination (κρίνειν) conveniently encapsulates the difference between how (i.e. with what result) perceivers and non-perceptive entities, respectively, are affected by perceptual objects – that is, exactly the difference for which the perceptive soul is supposed to account. But we have also seen that different views are available regarding how exactly discrimination is intended to fit within the assimilation model of perception as it is worked out primarily in An. 2.5. Furthermore, we have seen that these differences go hand in glove with differences in understanding how the perceptive soul fits in – that is, in what way it is supposed to be the sought-after first principle of perception. It is now time to dig deeper into the notion of perceptual discrimination (Sections 6.1, 6.2, and 6.3) and the account of it offered in An. 2.11 (Sections 6.4 and 6.5). The proposed interpretation of the latter will then lead us directly (in Sections 7.2 and 7.3) to a more concrete elaboration of the third potential approach to the role of the perceptive soul outlined in Section 5.5.

Let us begin from the question of meaning ascribed in the De Anima to κρίνειν. Theodor Ebert showed decisively how misleading it is to translate the verb as ‘to judge’. By ‘judging’ we primarily understand ‘passing judgment on’ something, or ‘contending’ – ‘asserting’ something in a way that can turn out to be either right or wrong. However, κρίνειν never means that – at least not in the De Anima.Footnote 1 Even in what Ebert (following Bonitz)Footnote 2 calls the ‘judicial sense’ (sensus iudicialis) of κρίνειν, it is better rendered as, for instance, ‘deciding’ a case.Footnote 3 Furthermore, according to Ebert, this is just a special use of κρίνειν; its ‘primary sense’ has even less to do with ‘judging’: what it means is rather ‘to discriminate’ or ‘to discern’.Footnote 4

In addition to these general observations, Ebert also made two claims that relate more specifically to Aristotle’s account of perception, suggesting that: (a) meanings dependent on the sensus iudicialis in Aristotle’s ‘psychological writings’ are exceptional and insignificant for the question of ‘what is done in perceiving’;Footnote 5 (b) in its primary ‘discriminative’ meaning, κρίνειν is a ‘three-place predicate … “S discriminates x from y” … symmetrical as to the second and the third place’.Footnote 6 Scholars have largely accepted both of these claims,Footnote 7 but each of them can be called into question.

The second claim implies that ‘what is done in perceiving’ is primarily discriminating two qualities from each other. One criticism of this implication runs as follows: it would seem that this meaning of discrimination cannot be ‘cognitively basic’, because it does not account for how we cognize each of the two qualities in the first place.Footnote 8 One could come to Ebert’s aid by biting the bullet and insisting that there is simply no more primary sense of cognizing x than discriminating it from some y and vice versa. But that idea is objectionable.

Let us consider the kind of scenario on which the phenomenon of ‘change blindness’ has been explored.Footnote 9 Assume that someone replaces the colour y from which, on Ebert’s view, I am discriminating the colour x with another colour z. One can argue that, irrespective of whether I notice the change, on Aristotle’s view, it will make no difference for the content and the meaning of my discrimination of x. If this is correct, there is something wrong with accepting y rather than z into the formula of discrimination (before the change). It is wrong, I contend, not because x was not discriminated from y, but rather because it was equally well discriminated from z, even though z was not actively perceived. One upshot is that, if discrimination is to be analysed as a three-place formula, then this formula cannot be ‘symmetrical as to the second and the third place’. This observation accords with the etymology of κρίνειν. The original meaning (IE *krei-) seems to be sifting or winnowing on a sieve.Footnote 10 This suggests that y need not be noticed, and that there need be no determinate y at all. If κρίνειν originally means something like ‘to select the valuable part (the grain) from an indiscriminate mass’,Footnote 11 then it is natural to expect that y involves all colours, while none of them is necessarily being perceived.

There are reasons to think that Ebert would reject this thought experiment. He insists that there is a ‘specific type of propositions involved in the propositional attitudes resulting from perception of special sensibles’.Footnote 12 The information contained in the basic acts of perceptual discrimination is non-copulative in the sense of involving exclusively items of the same ‘ontological group’, namely the modal-specific qualities themselves. Ebert argues that this information is entirely free from our everyday ‘belief that [for instance] colours somehow “stick” to their objects’.Footnote 13 In other words, he emphatically endorses the idea that, according to Aristotle, we primarily perceive the modal-specific qualities alone, and that these are only attached to their putative bearers somehow additionally – namely, by our ‘beliefs’. This allows Ebert to insist that a change in one part of the perceptual field necessarily involves changes in other parts. If, in contrast, we accept the idea (defended in Section 4.2) that, according to Aristotle, we also perceive, at least equally primarily, the bearers of perceptual qualities, then it becomes natural to believe that the change from y to z will have no consequences for our discrimination of x.

We shall later consider further reasons for rejecting Ebert’s formula. However, before inquiring deeper into the logic of perceptual discrimination, we must first discuss the other claim flagged above – that is, Ebert’s marginalization of the judicial sense of κρίνειν, which has not hitherto been questioned by scholars.

6.2 The Judicial Sense of Perceptual κρίνειν

According to Ebert, there is one single passage in the De Anima in which the meaning of perceptual κρίνειν is determined by the judicial context. This is the passage from An. 2.6, already quoted in Section 4.2, where Aristotle contrasts for the first time the infallibility of modal-specific perception with the fallibility of other kinds of perceiving:

each of them [i.e. the senses] κρίνει about (περί) these [i.e. the exclusive objects] and is not deceived about colour or about sound, but about what the coloured object is and where it is, or what the sounding object is or where it is.

(An. 2.6, 418a14–16)

Recent translations tend to give κρίνειν in this passage the discriminative meaning, partly as a result of Ebert’s influence, it seems. However, Ebert himself took this passage to be the exception to the rule, arguing that κρίνειν here cannot be rendered in terms of ‘discriminating/discerning’.Footnote 14 The idea seems to be that one can very well say that ‘S judges about/of x’,Footnote 15 but it is not obvious what ‘S discriminates/discerns about/concerning x’ would mean,Footnote 16 and the preposition περί cannot be simply ignored.Footnote 17 Ebert, in any case, analysed this passage convincingly as employing κρίνειν in a well-established meaning derived from the judicial context, such that the best translation would be ‘each sense decides about these’.

Ebert is drawing here on a group of passages from Aristotle’s Politics, listed already by Bonitz, in which Aristotle uses the expression κρίνειν περί with the genitive in the sense of having the authority to decide some issue. More specifically, such an authority is standardly ascribed to the judge in matters that are not unambiguously determined (‘decided’) by the law.Footnote 18 The question of authority (who is κύριος, who is entitled to ἄρχειν, who is ὁ κρίνων or κρινῶν) often comes to the fore in these contextsFootnote 19 – so much so that on some occasions the correct translation of κρίνειν seems to be just ‘to have (judicial) authority’, as in a curious fragment from the Protrepticus where Aristotle says that the rational part of the soul ‘by nature governs and has (judicial) authority over us’ (κατὰ φύσιν ἄρχει καὶ κρίνει περὶ ἡμῶν).Footnote 20 Unlike in nature, political matters often feature more options about how the authority to decide various issues can be distributed.Footnote 21 However, Aristotle does not, of course, take the question of distribution to be arbitrary; there is a certain normativity involved, which implies that the judge, for instance, is correctly recognized as the authority to decide certain kinds of issues. So, the question of who is ὁ κρίνων or κρινῶν in a given matter is often to be understood as asking about the ultimate authority to which one ought to defer should any uncertainty arise.Footnote 22

Ebert argues that, in An. 2.6, Aristotle ‘makes each sense, as it were, sit as a judge, an arbiter upon its corresponding special sensibles’.Footnote 23 This is an important observation that has not, I think, been sufficiently appreciated. It can, however, be further shown that (1) An. 2.6 is not the single exception: there is at least one other important passage in the De Anima, overlooked by Ebert, which draws clearly on the judicial sense. Moreover, (2) the clear-cut dividing line drawn by Ebert between ‘the primary sense’ of κρίνειν on the one hand and meanings derived from its ‘judicial sense’ on the other is misleading. Rather, the judicial overtones come more or less into the foreground throughout the De Anima, without ever entirely disappearing; recognizing this fact is important if we are to understand correctly what is at stake when Aristotle characterizes perception as a case of κρίνειν.Footnote 24

The quoted passage from An. 2.6 deserves detailed attention because it is the passage in which Aristotle introduces the notion of κρίνειν into his account of perception (only two other passages mention κρίνειν in the rest of Book 2). However, this term does not appear suddenly or unexpectedly. Aristotle has already employed the notion of κρίνειν when addressing LKL in An. 1.5,Footnote 25 and this is hardly accidental because Theophrastus uses κρίνειν fairly often for what his predecessors thought (or should have thought) is achieved in perceiving.Footnote 26 In An. 1.5, Aristotle raises an objection against the assumption that, if the perceiver is to know (γνωρίζειν) – that is, to κρίνειν – two opposites, such as black (dark) and white (pale), she must contain them both. In the Empedoclean picture, for instance, it means that she must contain passages of both water and fire. This assumption, Aristotle argues, is idle, for one of the opposites would be sufficient:

But even if it were necessary to compose the soul out of the elements, it would by no means be necessary to compose it out of all. For one member of the contrariety is sufficient to κρίνειν both itself and what is contrary to it. For by the straight we know (γινώσκομεν) both it and the bent, because the straight edge (ὁ κανών) is the judge (κριτής) of both, while the bent is [the judge] neither of itself nor of the straight.

(An. 1.5, 411a2–7)

The idea seems to be that the straight edge,Footnote 27 so to speak, ‘makes’ (or serves to make) authoritative, and, indeed, objective assessments whether something is straight or bent – much like a judge is the ultimate authority in deciding whether something is just or unjust. This agrees with the original meaning of κρίνειν as sieving: the sieve has an undisputable, perfectly objective authority with regard to isolating grain. Mutatis mutandis, Aristotle expects a successful theory of perception to explain how the senses can be the ultimate and infallible authority with regard to modal-specific qualities.Footnote 28 Moreover, he seems to be implying that at least some proponents of the LKL principle were already attempting to offer this kind of explanation, albeit not successfully.

So, what kind of authority exactly is being ascribed to the senses here? Theophrastus’ De Sensibus articulates a contrast between two different understandings of perceptual κρίνειν as a part of the overarching contrast between LKL and the idea that contrary is known by contrary (CKC).Footnote 29 The Empedoclean version of LKL, as construed by Theophrastus, provides a perfectly objective and impartial account of perceptual κρίνειν: the passages of water are such that only effluences of water fit into them and the passages of fire are such that only effluences of fire fit into them, so that there is effectively no room for error or anything ‘subjective’ with regard to identifying the black (dark) and the white (light) colour of external objects. The Anaxagorean version of CKC, in contrast, makes perceptivity directly dependent on the actual state of the subject: we perceive and discriminate, for instance, the drinkable out in the world by the briny in us (and so only as long as there is something briny and thirsty in us). Anaxagoras, to be sure, still ascribes a remarkable authority to the senses in determining the objective features of things (the account is not relativist or sceptical); only the range of accessible features becomes dependent on the current state of the perceiver’s body, because we perceive only what we lack.Footnote 30

This background provides a further reason for Aristotle’s focus on LKL in the De Anima:Footnote 31 in contrast to CKC, it can be presented as attempting to develop an account of perceptual κρίνειν that is entirely objective and impartial, a task that Aristotle is interested in taking over. As presented by Theophrastus, the Anaxagorean CKC would not be helpful in this respect, because it does not appreciate the impartiality of the rudimentary perceptual κρίνειν. That seems to be why Aristotle makes a different contrast central to the discussion he undertakes of his predecessors’ views on knowing – namely, the contrast with the Anaxagorean account of νοῦς as entirely impassive.Footnote 32 It is that position, and not CKC, which provides a genuine alternative to LKL with regard to accounting for the objective and impartial cognition achieved in perceiving. This alternative is not absent in Theophrastus’ presentation – but only marginal attention is paid to it. Theophrastus alludes to an alternative interpretation of Anaxagoras on κρίνειν when discussing Clidemus in chapter 38. Here, the idea seems to be that none of the senses really κρίνει anything; they only send the affections further to something else, namely νοῦς, which alone is capable of κρίνειν.Footnote 33 Again, the account seems to be modelled on a judicial situation in which certain questions are deferred to a judge for decision. The presumption is, in any case, that the cognition achieved by Anaxagorean νοῦς is at least as objective and impartial as the one provided by LKL. That seems to be why Aristotle contrasts in the De Anima precisely this kind of account with LKL: both accounts can be presented as agreeing on what is achieved in perceiving – namely, a perfectly objective and impartial cognition – but disagreeing on how it is achieved.Footnote 34

If this observation is correct, then it sheds additional light on the two intuitions that we identified (in Sections 1.4 and 2.7) behind the two horns of the key puzzle in An. 1.2. They can now be spelled out as two intuitions about the source and the nature of the judicial authority to be ascribed to perceivers. The Unbiasedness/Externality Requirement can be seen as drawing on the idea that, for something to have judicial authority over a certain question, it is necessary for that thing to be absolutely unbiased and not to be involved in it in any way whatsoever. It seems to be the same kind of intuition as the one occasionally articulated by Aristotle that no one rightly κρίνει things concerning himself. This is, for instance, why medical doctors are often unable to treat themselves properly.Footnote 35 The Acquaintance/Contact Requirement, on the other hand, would be drawing on a very different intuition about the source of a judicial authority – namely, that in some areas at least, it is not possible to decide the question without being intimately acquainted with the matter, for it is only by having, or being able to have, personal experience with what is at stake that one is able to arrive at the requisite understanding.Footnote 36 One model for this intuition about the source of judicial authority would be the idea of σύμβολα (which Aristotle associates with Empedocles).Footnote 37 To decide on some matter, I already need, so to speak, to have one of the σύμβολα in my possession (say, a past impression of a scar) because that is the only way to identify the decisive σύμβολον (a scar) in the matter under consideration. Similarly, the fire in the eye is like one half of a die (tessera hospitalis) that perfectly fits into the other half, represented by all the fire found in the external world, so that perceptual discrimination is like a case of a guest-friend (ξένος) recognizing his guest-friend (ξένος).

The two intuitions are thus very different, but what they have in common is their concern with the kind of authority that can decide a matter under consideration in a perfectly just manner – that is, to assess it objectively as it truly is. Aristotle shares this concern (unless we say he is projecting it onto his predecessors) and seems to think that there is something right about both intuitions, although each of them was muddied by errors committed by earlier thinkers. The demand of unbiasedness, on the one hand, must not be absolutized in the Anaxagorean manner, because that would cripple the alleged judge from any contact with the thing on which she is supposed to decide. The ‘symbolic’ idea of κρίνειν, on the other hand, reifies the requisite likeness in such a way that it leads to unacceptable results, as exposed in An. 1.5. Aristotle already suggests an amendment in the quoted passage (411a2–7): the judicial authority must be rather like that of the straight edge which allows us to identify reliably not only straight but also bent things. This amendment, as we shall see, is then further developed in the final section of An. 2.11. Aristotle’s aim here is, arguably, to provide an account of perceptual κρίνειν that would preserve what is true about each disputing side, while preventing their respective shortcomings.

More could be said about the ‘judicial’ overtones of perceptual κρίνειν. They become even more prevalent against the background of Aristotle’s engagement, particularly in Metaph. Γ.5–6 (and Κ.6), with the ‘narrow’ Protagoreanism, as developed and discussed in Plato’s Theaetetus, which is largely about the judicial authority of the senses.Footnote 38 The Protagoreans, on the one hand, insist that every perceiver contains a perfect criterion (κριτήριον) and measure (μέτρον), which makes her an ultimate infallible authority (κριτής, ὁ κρίνων) in the matter of what is perceived, albeit only insofar as it is perceived by her and so appearing to her.Footnote 39 Socrates, on the other hand, draws into question the very authority of the senses to decide about truth.Footnote 40 Aristotle emphatically asserts that the senses, in a healthy condition, are a perfect criterion (κριτήριον) and measure (μέτρον) for deciding (κρίνειν) about truth, the assessments of which cannot be further questioned in any meaningful way (contra Socrates), while insisting that what the senses access is an objective, and not merely a relative, truth (contra Protagoras).Footnote 41

The senses, in a healthy condition, are an objective and impartial authority, albeit only in the narrowly limited domain of modal-specific qualities. Indeed, Aristotle insists that the senses are the ultimate authority (κυρίον) in this domain in a sense that Socrates wishes to reserve for expert knowledge. Although our senses may lead us astray in causing us to believe, for instance, that the wine that is so sweet tonight will still be sweet tomorrow, there is no error possible about the perceived sweetness of sweet things itself:

the sweet, such as it is when it exists, has never changed; [the sense of taste] is always right about it, and that which is going to be sweet is of necessity just such a nature.

(Metaph. Γ.5, 1010b23–6)Footnote 42

Aristotle’s account of perceptual κρίνειν and its first principle in the De Anima can, then, be understood as effectively addressing an obvious objection that one may raise against his optimistic epistemology of perception as outlined in Metaph. Γ.5–6 and Κ.6. The grievance is that such an objective and impartial κρίνειν is, on the level of perception at least, simply impossible, and that no such authority can meaningfully be ascribed to the senses.Footnote 43 In the De Anima, Aristotle blunts at least one edge of this criticism by identifying the first explanatory principles on the basis of which this kind of perceptual κρίνειν can be scientifically explained.

If this is, indeed, the background against which the notion of κρίνειν in An. 1.5 should be understood, then it confirms the centrality of the judicial sense of the verb. However, even without this wider context, the passage quoted from An. 1.5 is sufficient to suggest that it is more difficult than Ebert claimed to distinguish between the meanings of κρίνειν that are and those that are not derived from the sensus iudicialis. In the first sentence, κρίνειν can very well be translated as ‘to discriminate’, but in the second sentence the word κριτής (in whatever way it is translated) clearly evokes the judicial context. Thus, the passage strongly suggests that there is a continuity between the two meanings that Ebert wanted to separate.Footnote 44 This continuity agrees well with the original meaning of κρίνειν as sieving, which is a (non-propositional) kind of discrimination involving a perfectly objective authority.

Aristotle’s judicial use of κρίνειν in An. 2.6 is, thus, far from being an exception that could be put aside when we attempt to understand his account of perceptual κρίνειν and of ‘what is done in perceiving’. The notion of κρίνειν introduced here rather encapsulates the task that Aristotle wishes to accomplish in what follows, including, crucially, the account of the ‘discriminative mean’ in An. 2.11.

6.3 Discrimination of the Imperceptible

As noted above, Aristotle’s use of the κρίνειν vocabulary in the De Anima is surprisingly sparse given how important a concept it is to his theory (as is broadly agreed by interpreters). Within An. 2.7–3.2, there are no more than two occurrences of it, besides the passage on the discriminative mean in An. 2.11 and the final section of An. 3.2 (on which, see Sections 6.4 and 6.6, respectively). These two occurrences are worth briefly commenting on here because they have a direct bearing on the question of the logic of perceptual discrimination, as well as on how the verbs κρίνειν and αἰσθάνεσθαι relate to each other. More specifically, these passages suggest that κρίνειν is a broader notion.

In both passages (An. 2.10, 422a20–31 and 3.2, 425b20–2), Aristotle employs the verb κρίνειν to articulate a thought that he elsewhere expresses without mentioning κρίνειν. The idea is that, for instance, sight is of both the visible and the invisible, hearing is of both the audible and the inaudible, and so on. Aristotle makes this claim four times within An. 2.7–3.2 and he never phrases it in terms of, say, sight seeing the invisible.Footnote 45 However, in both passages in which he employs κρίνειν, he affirms that sight discriminates (κρίνει) – or that we discriminate (κρίνομεν) by sight – ‘the invisible’, namely darkness. This nuance should not be overlooked: the notion of discriminating under individual sense modalities seems to be broader than the notion of perceiving under them – as understood throughout An. 2.5–12 where, for instance, ‘perceiving by sight’ is equivalent to ‘seeing’. It is true that at An. 3.2, 425b20–2, Aristotle employs the notion of ‘perceiving by sight’ in a broader sense than ‘seeing’ that appears to be co-extensive with the notion of ‘discriminating by sight’.Footnote 46 However, this seems to be an innovation vis-à-vis An. 2.5–12. Throughout these early chapters, ‘perceiving by sight’ is treated as equivalent to ‘seeing’, and so it would be wrong to say that sight perceives darkness, although sight is of darkness and discriminates it. One of the four passages making this claim (An. 2.11, 424a10–15) immediately follows Aristotle’s account of perceptual discrimination at An. 2.11, 423b31–424a10, and so the described mismatch between perception and discrimination is not unlikely to have a bearing on it.

Before considering that passage, however, let me add two preliminary observations concerning the logic of perceptual κρίνειν. First, the two passages insisting that sight discriminates darkness speak against the idea of κρίνειν as a three-place predicate: when I am ‘discriminating’ darkness, I am obviously not discriminating it from any actively perceived colour or light that would, thus, be symmetrically discriminated from darkness. Second, in the first of these passages (An. 2.10, 422a20–31) the meaning of κρίνειν seems, once more, to be directly connected to the judicial context. Again, the question is about distributing authorities, and the claim that ‘sight κρίνει this [i.e. darkness] as well’ could plausibly be paraphrased as ‘sight is also the authority to decide whether it is dark’. Indeed, given that this is the first occurrence of κρίνειν after An. 2.6, Aristotle’s claim is naturally read in direct connection with it: sight is not only the authority to decide about colours, but also the authority to decide about invisibility (darkness), and similarly for the other sense modalities. If this is correct, then the passage confirms that the sensus iudicialis plays a more central role in Aristotle’s argument than is usually assumed.Footnote 47

6.4 Discrimination within the Assimilation Model

Let us now finally turn to the part of An. 2.11 in which Aristotle introduces the notion of a ‘discriminative mean’. Most of An. 2.11 has been dedicated to defending the thesis that flesh is not the organ, but merely the medium of touch. The concept of the ‘discriminative mean’ is then introduced in the context of tactile blind spots.Footnote 48 Aristotle argues for the existence of these blind spots (at 423b26–424a4) drawing on the classification of tangible qualities as distinguishing features of bodies qua bodies (i.e. qualities that all bodies necessarily have to some degree),Footnote 49 combined with the assimilation model of perception as developed in An. 2.5. The fact that Aristotle proceeds in this way is convenient for our purposes because the passage explicitly embeds the account of perceptual discrimination within the assimilation model:

(i) The perceptive organ responsible for them [i.e. the tangible qualities], that is, that which is capable of touching and in which the perceptive capacity called touch is primarily present, is a bodily part that is such in capacity [as the tangible objects are in fulfilment]. For perceiving is a kind of being affected, and so, what the agent is like in fulfilment, such it is making the other thing [i.e. the perceptive organ] which is [such] in capacity. (ii) That is why we do not perceive what is equally warm and cold or hard and soft [as our body] but only the extremes because the perceptive capacity is a sort of mean of the contrariety in perceptual objects. And that is why one [or: it, i.e. the perceptive organ] discriminates the perceptual objects. For what is in a mean state is capable of discriminating, because with respect to each [object] it comes to be the other extreme. (iii) And just as that which is going to perceive what is white and what is black must be neither of them in fulfilment, while being in capacity both (and similarly also for the other senses), so also in the case of touch it [i.e. that which is going to perceive hot and cold] must be neither hot nor cold.

(i) τὸ δὲ αἰσθητήριον αὐτῶν τὸ ἁπτικόν, καὶ ἐν ᾧ ἡ καλουμένη ἁφὴ ὑπάρχει αἴσθησις πρώτῳ, τὸ δυνάμει τοιοῦτόν ἐστι μόριον· τὸ γὰρ αἰσθάνεσθαι πάσχειν τι ἐστίν· ὥστε τὸ ποιοῦν, οἷον αὐτὸ ἐνεργείᾳ, τοιοῦτον ἐκεῖνο ποιεῖ δυνάμει ὄν. (ii) διὸ τοῦ ὁμοίως θερμοῦ καὶ ψυχροῦ, ἢ σκληροῦ καὶ μαλακοῦ, οὐκ αἰσθανόμεθα, ἀλλὰ τῶν ὑπερβολῶν, ὡς τῆς αἰσθήσεως οἷον μεσότητός τινος οὔσης τῆς ἐν τοῖς αἰσθητοῖς ἐναντιώσεως. καὶ διὰ τοῦτο κρίνει τὰ αἰσθητά. τὸ γὰρ μέσον κριτικόν· γίνεται γὰρ πρὸς ἑκάτερον αὐτῶν θάτερον τῶν ἄκρων· (iii) καὶ δεῖ ὥσπερ τὸ μέλλον αἰσθήσεσθαι λευκοῦ καὶ μέλανος μηδέτερον αὐτῶν εἶναι ἐνεργείᾳ, δυνάμει δ’ ἄμφω (οὕτω δὲ καὶ ἐπὶ τῶν ἄλλων), καὶ ἐπὶ τῆς ἁφῆς μήτε θερμὸν μήτε ψυχρόν.

(An. 2.11, 423b29–424a10)

The first thing to notice about this passage is that, although the account of the discriminative mean in (ii) is developed specifically with respect to touch, it seems to be intended to apply generally to all sense modalities, as suggested by the generalization in (iii) and confirmed by Aristotle’s later uses of μεσότης.Footnote 50 Just as the notion of mediation was introduced as applying primarily to sight and hearing and then extended, somewhat surprisingly, to all other senses, so the notion of the discriminative mean is introduced as applying primarily to touch before being extended to the remaining sense modalities.Footnote 51

Another salient feature of our passage is the exceptional clarity with which Aristotle distinguishes the material and the formal aspects of perceivers – that is, the bodily perceptive organs on the one hand, and the perceptive capacity of the soul, on the other. In (i) he explicitly distinguishes between the organ (αἰσθητήριον) of touch and the sense of touch (ἁφή), which is what makes the organ capable of touching (ἁπτικόν). The assimilation model from An. 2.5 is then clearly applied to the perceptive organ rather than the perceptive capacity, which aligns perfectly with An. 1.3–4.Footnote 52 This suggests that Aristotle is willing to tell us something important about the respective roles of the body and the soul.Footnote 53

Furthermore, there is no reason to assume that he is any less careful in this respect in (ii) and (iii). Yet, most translators and interpreters disregard the difference between μεσότης τις and τὸ μέσον in (ii): most often they are translated by the same word,Footnote 54 and even when not, the difference usually plays no role in interpretation.Footnote 55 Because it is αἴσθησις (apparently in the sense of the perceptive capacity, as a generalization of ἁφή) that is identified with μεσότης, however, (i) makes it natural to expect that the intended example of τὸ μέσον would be the organ as determined by the μεσότης, just as the organ of touch is ἁπτικόν owing to the ἁφή operative in it.Footnote 56 This is not to say that μεσότης could not be treated in a more relaxed manner as a case of τὸ μέσον; rather, the point is that the present context strongly suggests that Aristotle expects the reader to be sensitive to the difference between that which is in a mean state and the mean itself.Footnote 57

The final phrase of (i) clearly recalls the assimilation model from An. 2.5, and it has been interpreted in very different ways, depending on the literalist, spiritualist, or analogical understanding of the role of the perceptive organs from which interpreters have begun. However, the present passage brings into focus again how each of these approaches falls flat.Footnote 58 It is notoriously difficulty for spiritualism to account for the phenomenon of blind spots introduced in (ii) as a consequence of the assimilation model: if only a ‘spiritual’ acting is involved in perception, the claim that ‘that is why we do not perceive what is equally warm and cold’ would be a clear non sequitur.Footnote 59 If, on the other hand, the assimilation model was just about acquiring literal likeness, then the change that is supposed to underlie perception would effectively make it impossible. On becoming literally like the perceptual object, the organ would become unable to be affected by it and thus, as Aristotle clearly implies here, unable to perceive it.Footnote 60 The change supposed to bring perception about would, in fact, only produce a perceptual blind spot.Footnote 61 Finally, the analogical reading does not fare any better on this point (as observed in Section 4.6). If the way in which a perceptual object F acts on the perceiver consists in making it G (i.e. making it embody the same ratio in a different pair of contraries) and if the result of this acting is that the organ comes to be G, then, again, the change that is supposed to underlie perception makes it effectively impossible, for it implies that the organ cannot be further affected by the perceptual object F in the required way, and so that the organ cannot perceive F.

The interpretation of Aristotle’s first general account developed in Chapters 13 offers a viable alternative (spelled out in Section 4.6), and Aristotle’s phrasing in the present passage provides additional support for it. The perceptual object F is making (ποιεῖ) FFootnote 62 the organ, which is F in capacity (δυνάμει ὄν). Aristotle says nothing here about the result of this making. However, combining this claim with the assertion that perceiving is a kind of being affected has an important implication that could have hardly escaped Aristotle’s notice: throughout the time of perceiving F, the respective organ must remain F in capacity; indeed, to continue being affected, and so perceiving, the organ must remain unlike the object (i.e. not F in fulfilment).

The present passage is not the only additional support for the proposed interpretation of the assimilation model. The same idea can, arguably, be found in a convoluted sentence from An. 2.10 describing how the tongue, as the alleged organ of taste, is affected by flavours:Footnote 63

ἀναγκαῖον ἄρα ὑγρανθῆναι τὸ δυνάμενον μὲν ὑγραίνεσθαι σωζόμενον μὴ ὑγρὸν δὲ τὸ γευστικὸν αἰσθητήριον.

(An. 2.10, 422b3–5)

The syntax of this passage is uncertain and there are at least three ways to construe the sentence. The position of δέ calls for the insertion of a comma after σωζόμενον and suggests that this participle should be understood as a part of the μέν clause. This leaves the meaning of σωζόμενον underdetermined. (1) On one reading, it tends to be translated along the lines of ‘without being harmed’ and the sentence is taken to be saying at best something very vague.Footnote 64 But Aristotle is more likely to have something more precise in mind, namely, (2) that the organ is moistened in such a way that it is preserved as being capable of being moistened: that is, upon being moistened, it does not lose its capacity for being moistened.Footnote 65 The δέ clause (‘not being moist’) would then seem to be not simply describing the state before being moistened, but rather the state that needs to be preserved also when the tongue is being moistened. (3) Finally, a third construal that would elucidate this idea even more clearly would place a comma before σωζόμενον and take it already to be a part of the δέ clause. (This does not seem quite right stylistically, but it can hardly be excluded as a possibility in a manuscript of Aristotle’s work.) The sentence would then be saying that the organ of taste is moistened as something (a) that can be moistened (μέν), but (b) that, upon being moistened, is preserved as not moist (δέ).

What follows at 422b5–10 seems to support (2) or (3) against (1). Aristotle explains here that the tongue cannot properly taste anything if it is itself too moist: what happens then is that we do not really taste, but rather experience an after-taste on our tongue. This suggests that, although tasting involves the tongue being moistened, it must at the same time be preserved as itself not being (too) moist, because otherwise the moistening would eventually lead to the tongue becoming incapable of being moistened, and thus incapable of tasting, for it would acquire an (excessive) moisture (and, with it, apparently a flavour) of its own. Under (2) or (3), the passage fits perfectly with the interpretation of preservative πάσχειν proposed in Chapters 13,Footnote 66 as well as the reading of (i) in the quoted passage from An. 2.11 proposed above.

Returning to the 2.11 passage, I have been arguing that Aristotle describes here what happens in perceiving in terms of the perceptual object making the perceptive organ like itself, with the organ, however, having its unlikeness preserved as a condition of being further affected, and so of continued perceiving. If that is true, then (i) spells out only a part of the assimilation model as developed in An. 2.5: it does not say anything explicit about the likeness acquired by the perceiver for the time of perceiving. And there is a good reason for this omission: it is, I shall argue, because Aristotle is going to tell us something new and important about the likeness in (ii). Put very roughly: the perceptive organ must not be assimilated to the perceptual object in the sense of acquiring a material quality of its own, because only then can it receive a quality of the external perceptual object. My suggestion in the following section will be that the notion of the ‘discriminative mean’ in (ii) is intended precisely to explain how the latter kind of likeness (further spelled out in An. 2.12 in terms of forms without the matter) comes to be present in the perceptive organ without compromising its neutrality.Footnote 67

6.5 The Discriminative Mean

In (ii), Aristotle argues that the perceptive capacity (αἴσθησις), such as touch,Footnote 68 is a certain μεσότης of the respective contrariety; this is why something or someone κρίνει the perceptual objects: καὶ διὰ τοῦτο κρίνει τὰ αἰσθητά. The grammatical subject is not expressed, but it clearly refers to the same kind of thing as ‘τὸ μέσον’ in what follows: τὸ γὰρ μέσον κριτικόν. Usually, interpreters assume that the grammatical subject of κρίνει is the μεσότης from the preceding sentence; this leads them, understandably, to treat ‘μεσότης’ as a case of ‘τὸ μέσον’. However, this is not the only possible reading.Footnote 69 The sentence with κρίνει can also be taken as an absolute construction, ‘that is why one discriminates’, playing the same role as the first person plural at the beginning of (ii) ‘that is why we do not perceive’.Footnote 70 Alternatively, the grammatical subject may be τὸ ἁπτικόν from 423b30, to which Aristotle has already referred back by the demonstrative pronoun ἐκεῖνο at 424a2.

Both of these readings suggest that the intended instance of τὸ μέσον capable of κρίνειν on account of μεσότης is not this μεσότης itself. Rather, it is the organ in which this μεσότης – that is, the perceptive capacity (αἴσθησις) in question – is primarily present, as outlined in the first sentence of (i).Footnote 71 This reading is supported by the beginning of (iii) where Aristotle talks of ‘that which is going to perceive white and black’ (τὸ μέλλον αἰσθήσεσθαι λευκοῦ καὶ μέλανος). He says that this must be neither black nor white in fulfilment but both in capacity, and he clearly compares this with what he has already said in (i) about the organ of touch (it is neither hot nor cold in fulfilment). Accordingly, τὸ μέλλον αἰσθήσεσθαι must be the perceptive organ. Now, there would be a strange shift if Aristotle were not also referring to the organ in the preceding sentence concerning τὸ μέσον. Rather, throughout the whole passage, he seems to be carefully distinguishing between that which can perceive, can touch, can κρίνειν, on the one hand, and that on account of which it can do so, on the other. The passage thus seems to be perfectly in line with the ‘Rylean passage’ in treating discrimination as something performed by an animal on account of its soul.Footnote 72 And this is no accident for, I shall argue, Aristotle is telling us something very important here about how the soul makes the animal capable of discriminating and perceiving.

Aristotle claims that the perceptive capacity is ‘a sort of mean’. This claim has been interpreted in various ways – of which I shall mention only two.Footnote 73 According to Klaus Corcilius, Aristotle characterizes the perceptive soul here as a neutral value of each range, which is ‘a metaphysical given’ for AristotleFootnote 74 and is localized in a non-metaphorical way ‘somewhere in the heart’.Footnote 75 As such, the soul can serve literally as the end point of perceptual motions transmitted, according to An. 1.4, ‘up until’ the soul.Footnote 76 Upon their arrival at this spatial point in the heart, ‘a sort of contact between body and soul’ is established and thus also a literal ‘contiguity of the soul with the incoming … motions’.Footnote 77 Such a juxtaposition generates a contrast between the neutral value (i.e. the soul) and the value of the incoming motion. Because the former value is neutral, the contrast just is the manifestation of the incoming value: it is the perceptual object in activity – the form without the matter of the external object acting on the senses. It is in this context that Corcilius suggests an alternative to Ebert’s three-place model of perceptual discrimination: the perceptive soul qua mean discriminates the quality of the perceptual object from itself.Footnote 78 Much can be said in favour of this account. It accomplishes what has rarely been achieved by providing a concrete model of the perceptive soul’s causality that is neither circular nor compromises the soul’s impassivity. I shall, accordingly, discuss this view further below.

In a recent paper, Roberto Grasso offers a different interpretation of μεσότης. He claims that it refers to a state of the perceptive organ resulting from two opposite agencies cancelling each other out: (1) the agency of the perceptual object assimilating the organ to itself and (2) the counterbalancing agency of the organ. (2) neutralizes (1), and so retains the organ in its neutral state. The μεσότης is just this state ‘that results from opposite extremes’ – a ‘zero vector sum’.Footnote 79 I shall argue below that Aristotle does indeed have a homeostatic mechanism in mind in our passage; however, I do not share Grasso’s view that the passage is simply about physiology.Footnote 80 As noted above, Aristotle seems to be promising to tell us something about the role of the soul. And, indeed, it is difficult to read the sentence about μεσότης as not concerning the perceptive soul. It is αἴσθησις that Aristotle identifies with ‘a sort of mean’, and although the word αἴσθησις can also refer to the activity of perceiving and is occasionally used to denote the ensouled organ, the present context strongly suggests that Aristotle has the perceptive capacity in mind (see 423b31).Footnote 81 It is difficult to see how the claim that αἴσθησις is a mean could be read as a claim about the preserved physiological state.Footnote 82

However, if Aristotle does have the perceptive capacity in mind, how should we interpret its status ‘as a sort of mean’ and its role in perceptual discrimination? One problem with the first mentioned interpretation is that, as on most other interpretations, it disregards the difference between ‘μεσότης’ and ‘τὸ μέσον’. If I am right about Aristotle’s intention behind this difference, then it is not the perceptive capacity itself that is said to discriminate. Rather, Aristotle is saying that the organ (or the living being endowed with this organ) discriminates on account of the perceptive capacity operating in it ‘as a sort of mean’ and so determining the organ as ‘being in a mean state’. If this is the case, then there is some hope that we need not take the perceptive capacity as ‘a sort of mean’ to be a static constant whose mode of presence in the perceptive organ cannot be further analysed. Instead, a story can be told regarding how the μεσότης determines the organ as τὸ μέσον and thus makes it capable of discriminating. One reason for preferring this interpretation, I submit, is that it need not assume that the soul is non-metaphorically located in a spatial point ‘somewhere in the heart’.Footnote 83

Such a non-metaphorical localization of the soul, which underlies the idea of a contact between the body and the soul and a contiguity between the soul and the incoming motion, seems to be at odds with the spirit of An. 1.3–4. Aristotle’s very first argument against the soul itself undergoing a change was that it would imply that the soul is in a place.Footnote 84 That was considered to be patently absurd, and Aristotle never suggests that the idea of the soul itself having a position (θέσις), like a point, is more acceptable than that of it having a place (τόπος). Moreover, Aristotle’s definition of touch in Phys. 5.3 implies that only extended entities, not points, can be in touch with other beings.Footnote 85 And, although his commitment to there being a touch between the mover and the moved leads him to introduce the notion of a non-reciprocal touching in GC 1.6 as a way of accounting for the case of unmoved movers,Footnote 86 it is not at all obvious that this should be understood in terms of the unmoved mover having a determinate position.Footnote 87 Accordingly, ascribing such a position to the soul would still be objectionable as a way of assimilating it to spatial entities (although not bodies) and would thus go against the thrust of An. 1.3–4.Footnote 88

In my understanding of the passage, Aristotle is proposing an entirely different model of the soul’s involvement in perceptual discrimination. The soul figures in it as ‘a sort of mean’ not in the sense of a static constant, literally contiguous with the incoming motions, but rather in the sense of dynamically determining the perceptive organ as being in a mean state and so being discriminative, as it ‘comes to be the other extreme’ with respect to each object. This account can fill precisely the gap in the assimilation model left open in (i): it contains the key to understanding the sense in which the perceiver is assimilated to the perceptual object acting on her, while remaining neutral, and thereby capable of being further affected.

The persisting neutrality of the organ is, I suggest, captured exactly by its description as τὸ μέσον.Footnote 89 The most obvious case, which Aristotle seems to have primarily in mind here, is that of perceiving the heat and the cold. The cold air acts on my body by literally cooling it down. If I were a plant or a kettle of water, this acting would result simply in the lowering of my temperature, not in perception. The reason for this would be exactly my lack of the requisite mean, as Aristotle says in An. 2.12: the reason why plants do not perceive, although they are cooled and warmed, is that ‘they do not have a mean (μεσότης)’; they ‘are affected with the matter’, rather than receiving the forms of perceptual objects.Footnote 90 Having the requisite mean, I contend, implies precisely that the air acting on my body does not result in the lowering of my temperature, but rather in something else. Presumably, my temperature remains exactly the same (with smaller or larger local oscillations) owing to a homeostatic reaction that counterbalances the agency of the external object acting on me.Footnote 91 This homeostatic mechanism is what guarantees that I can continue being affected by the same object and thus can continue perceiving it.Footnote 92

But there is more to be said. It is not just that my organ remains in its neutral state: when doing so, ‘it comes to be the other extreme’ with respect to the perceptual object acting on it, and so it discriminates this object. Aristotle seems to be capturing here the sense in which the perceiver is assimilated to the perceptual object acting on her, while remaining neutral with respect to it. The sense of ‘coming to be’ that Aristotle has in mind can hardly be a mere Cambridge change. He cannot mean just that τὸ ἁπτικόν ‘comes to be the other extreme’ with respect to anything we might wish to compare it with (just as something tepid ‘becomes’ warm in comparison with ice, and cold in comparison with boiling water). This would not explain why τὸ ἁπτικόν is κριτικόν, which is exactly what Aristotle is trying to explain. Rather, it seems, when affected by something cold, τὸ ἁπτικόν ‘comes to be the other extreme’, and exactly the other extreme, in the sense that, to remain a μέσον, it must undergo a certain amount of internal heating that corresponds exactly to the amount of cooling caused by the external object.

The key point here is that the counterbalancing reaction is – in a way that is yet to be explored – governed by the perceptive capacity that serves, in this precise sense, as the mean of the organ that defines the normative state in which the organ is always retained (or to which it returns as quickly as possible). This homeostatic mechanism provides a model for the involvement of the soul in perceiving that is not circular, does not compromise the soul’s impassivity, and need not ascribe a literal spatial position to the soul. Rather, the perceptive soul can be understood as being a kind of unmoved mover, which ‘meets’ the incoming motions not by becoming literally contiguous with them, but by its ‘acting’ on the organ, with the result that this ‘acting’ is directly determined by the agency of the perceptual object. This, I submit, is how the relevant quality comes to be present in the perceiver exactly as a measured quality of the external object rather than as a quality of the perceiver herself.Footnote 93

An important point to notice about this model is that the soul cannot be absolutely impassive (like Anaxagoras’ or Aristotle’s divine νοῦς). Crucially, it is coincidentally affected by perceptual objects insofar as its organ is affected. Moreover, its activity is occasioned by the agency of the perceptual object and, indeed, is fully determined by it to the extent that the counterbalancing reaction does nothing more and nothing less than perfectly neutralize the agency of the perceptual object. In this sense, the activity can be described as receptive: it consists in nothing other than ‘receiving’ (in an inverted form comparable to a wax imprint) the quality of an external perceptual object. However, it is crucial that the reception does not take place in the perceptive soul itself. The soul does not ‘absorb’ the quality of the object into itself, not even in the etiolated sense of undergoing a kind of ‘spiritual’ alteration. Rather, the quality is received in the soul’s very acting on the organ, and so the soul is not affected in any non-coincidental way that would compromise its impassivity.Footnote 94 We shall return to this point in Sections 7.4 and 7.5 when discussing the passages in An. that may seem to compromise the perceptive soul’s impassivity.

It is interesting, for the overall reconstruction, to note that the notion of μεσότης, when interpreted in the proposed way, can be directly related to the notion of ἀπάθεια that Aristotle ascribes to ‘that which can perceive’ in An. 3.4, drawing on An. 2.5. Characterizing the perceptive capacity as a mean comes very close to describing it in terms of an impassivity of the organ along the lines of Metaph. Δ.12 and Θ.1 – that is, in terms of a power for resisting a certain (detrimental) kind of being affected, which is a prerequisite, or even a constituent, of a capacity for being affected in an excellent way.Footnote 95 It is exactly because the organ resists – in a determinate way owing to the soul – undergoing the change that non-perceptive entities would normally undergo when so affected that it is assimilated to the perceptual object in the requisite way (i.e. that it receives a quality of the external perceptual object not as a quality of its own but exactly as a quality of that object).

This goal is achieved by means of a homeostatic mechanism, through which the agency of perceptual objects is very precisely measured.Footnote 96 The quality comes to be present in the ensouled organ as a result of this measurement: as a precisely determined proportion (λόγος) defining the quality in question. We could compare the way of measurement that Aristotle appears to have in mind here with weighing:Footnote 97 τὸ ἁπτικόν is like a qualitative balance scale with one pan turned towards the perceptual objects and the other pan turned, so to speak, towards the soul; it resembles the beam of a balance scale continually brought to equilibrium by a mechanism governed by the soul as its unmoved mover. This weighing, in which the ‘weight’ of the perceptual object is continually determined, is the activity of perceiving – as a way of being affected by the perceptual object that is a case of discriminating that object.

The metaphor of weighing in the last paragraph was intentionally embellished as a way of emphasizing one question raised by the proposed account, namely: how exactly should we understand the alleged agency of the soul? It must, of course, not be understood as turning the soul into a quasi-bodily agent – that would be an obvious failure by the criteria set out in An. 1.3–4. Rather, as the nutritive soul, it is an impassive agent, much like an artFootnote 98 – with the difference that it resembles not so much the art of carpentry but rather a measuring art.Footnote 99 That, of course, does not fully answer the question, which will need to be discussed in its own right in Section 7.3. For now, however, the point is only that there is no prima facie reason for rejecting such an account of the perceptive soul as an efficient cause.Footnote 100 What needs to be discussed is how exactly the model Aristotle develops for the nutritive soul can be adapted to perception.Footnote 101

Another question that must be addressed (in Section 7.2) is how far the proposed account can be extended from touch to the other sense modalities. Assuming that it works fairly well for the heat and the cold, one might wonder whether there is a way of making it plausible for other perceptual objects, as suggested by (iii) in the quoted passage from An. 2.11.

If we assume, for now, that these questions can be satisfyingly answered, we can see what kind of solution Aristotle provides in An. 2.11 to the key puzzle from An. 1.2 when rephrased in terms of κρίνειν (as proposed in Section 6.2). The judicial authority of perceivers is not based on any ‘symbolic’ relation to their objects – that is, it is not based on a static likeness preceding perception (as in the model of a guest-friend recognizing his guest-friend). Rather, to possess the requisite judicial authority, the senses need to be more unbiased than that: the perceiver must be, and remain throughout the duration of perceiving, neutral with respect to the perceived object and any other perceptual object within the given range.Footnote 102 However, this neutrality does not preclude the perceiver being in contact with the perceived object, and, indeed, being intimately acquainted with it, by means of a dynamic likeness constantly re-established by a measuring homeostatic reaction to the agency of the perceived object. The perceptive organ measures the perceived object not as a static straight edge (κανών), but rather by constantly receiving, so to speak, the perfect measure of the object from the object itself.

This may explain why Aristotle can say both that the perceiver measures perceptual objects and that she is measured by them.Footnote 103 The perceiver measures the objects in the sense that, without the homeostatic reaction governed by the soul there would be no perceptual measuring whatsoever. However, the perceiver is also measured by these objects insofar as she does not contain any fixed measure (like κανών) of them: she is rather receiving the measure from the objects themselves throughout the activity of perceiving them, as they constantly determine, by their agency, the precise counterbalancing reaction governed by the soul.

6.6 The Single Mean and the Core of Perceptual Discrimination

Let us now step back from the details of the proposed reading of An. 2.11, 423b25–424a15. The interpretation of this passage offered in Sections 6.4 and 6.5 fits well with the overall picture of perceptual discrimination in the De Anima that I have been developing. What matters for now is that the passage neither supports the three-place model of perceptual discrimination, nor does it necessarily imply the alternative two-place model proposed by Corcilius in which the soul qua neutral value discriminates the quality of the perceptual object from itself. Instead, what Aristotle has in mind when he speaks of discriminating darkness, for instance, is an act of singling it out as being distinct from all potential objects of vision, that is, colours – plus apparently (intense) light in which no colour can be seen. This will also hold for colours themselves and for the other modal-specific qualities: when a colour is discriminated, it means that it is identified as just being this colour and no other; as on a sieve, it is discerned from the background of all potential colours (and objects of sight in general).

One can worry at this point whether the case of discriminating darkness and the case of discriminating colours can really fall under the same notion of discrimination. After all, we have seen that in An. 2.11 Aristotle embeds the account of perceptual discrimination firmly in the assimilation model and spells it out in terms of coming to be the other extreme. But it is obvious that none of this happens in the case of darkness. So, how could ‘discrimination’ mean the same thing here?

I think the answer is contained in the passages that have often been taken to support the three-place model of discrimination. The question at An. 3.2, 426b12–14 is what makes us capable of discriminating various qualities – of the same or of different modalities – in relation to each other (πρὸς ἕκαστον), and so to ‘perceive that they differ’. On the most general level, I take Aristotle’s answer to be that it is because the perceptive capacity is a single capacity.Footnote 104 Later in An. 3.7, the claim is formulated in yet stronger terms: that ‘up until’ which all the perceptual motions, of various modalities, extend is a numerically single mean (μία μεσότης) with more than one being.Footnote 105 Thus, when Aristotle identified a perceptive capacity such as touch as ‘a sort of mean of the contrariety in perceptual objects’, what he was describing was, effectively, just one of the beings (or aspects) of a more complex entity numerically identical for all sense modalities, and beyond.Footnote 106

The idea of a numerically single mean seems to be directly connected to Aristotle’s account of perceiving the bearers of perceptual qualities, as discussed in Section 4.2. Furthermore, it can help us understand the discrimination of what is imperceptible. Suppose that I am standing on a mountain in the midst of a cloudy moonless night, and I am, in Aristotle’s terms, perceptually discriminating darkness. What happens, I take it, is this: I am perceiving the air around me by touch and smell, while perhaps also hearing how it moves; that is, I am perceiving this curious three-dimensional thing that is the air surrounding me, and I am perceiving it by the single mean active in me under several modalities at once. In the case of the three aforementioned modalities, the discriminated qualities of the air are all acting on me; and even one of them would be sufficient to make me perceive this thing (i.e. the surrounding air), because even one of them is sufficient to activate the single perceptive mean. As long as this mean is activated, albeit just by a single quality (say, the cold), it produces a holistic discrimination of its bearer. If the air makes no noise, then it cannot be heard, but it can be discriminated (under the auditory modality) as silent; and if there is no light present in it, it cannot be seen (or nothing can be seen through it), but it can be discriminated (under the visual modality) as dark; and so on. Thus, to return to our question: it seems true that all episodes of perceptual discrimination can be fitted into the assimilation model with the organ ‘coming to be the other extreme’ and so receiving a quality not as a quality of its own but as a quality of the external object acting on the perceiver; but it does not follow that the perceiver is assimilated to all the features of the perceptual object that she discriminates. There is sufficient room for discrimination of what is imperceptible, without any need to assume that this is an entirely different kind of discrimination or that it lacks any connection to the assimilation model.Footnote 107

This consideration also sheds some light on the phenomenon of tactile blind spots and on why, after presenting the account of the discriminative mean, Aristotle returns, in the final lines of An. 2.11 (424a10–15), to the topic of discrimination of what is imperceptible with an emphasis on what is non-tangible. One kind of the non-tangible is ‘that which has an entirely indistinct διαφορά of tangible qualities, such as the air’. Now, air can surely have a very strong tangible διαφορά, for instance, when it is very cold;Footnote 108 but it can also have no thermal διαφορά at all when it has the same level of heat as the perceiver’s body.Footnote 109 This applies to other objects as well. When a pot of water has exactly the same temperature as our body, we cannot feel it, for it coincides with our blind spot; but it is nonetheless an object of touch and we can, in line with An. 2.10, discriminate its temperature by touch. When I put my hand into the pot and am affected by its humidity, I use touch to discriminate not only this humidity but also the water’s non-tangible tepidity.Footnote 110

What leads scholars to interpret Aristotle’s account of perceptual discrimination in terms of a three-place model is primarily the final part of An. 3.2, where he discusses the question of how we discriminate various qualities in relation to each other (ἕκαστον τῶν αἰσθητῶν πρὸς ἕκαστον κρίνομεν, 426b13–14), which implies that ‘we perceive that they differ’. What Aristotle analyses here, I take it, is not a special case, but rather something that happens in all (or nearly all) cases of perceiving: we standardly perceive the external object simultaneously under a plurality of its qualitative aspects, which implies that we also, in a way, perceive that these qualities differ from each other (otherwise there would be no perceived plurality at all). In this sense, it is true that in perception we standardly discriminate between actively perceived qualities (of a single modality, as well as of different modalities). However, it does not follow that the basic, and explanatorily primary, kind of discrimination is conceived by Aristotle as a three-place predicate. We have already seen several pieces of evidence telling against this assumption. Moreover, the way in which Aristotle introduces his inquiry into simultaneous perception in An. 3.2 provides no support for such a claim, either. Rather, if anything, it provides an additional piece of evidence against it. Aristotle writes:

Each sense, being present in the perceptive organ qua perceptive organ, is of the underlying perceptual object and discriminates the διαφοραί of the underlying perceptual object, as, for instance, sight [discriminates] white and black, and taste [discriminates] sweet and bitter, and this is similar also in the case of the other senses. But since we discriminate both white and sweet and [we discriminate] all [perceived qualities] in relation to each other, there is something by which we also perceive that they differ.

ἑκάστη μὲν οὖν αἴσθησις τοῦ ὑποκειμένου αἰσθητοῦ ἐστίν, ὑπάρχουσα ἐν τῷ αἰσθητηρίῳ ᾗ αἰσθητήριον, καὶ κρίνει τὰς τοῦ ὑποκειμένου αἰσθητοῦ διαφοράς, οἷον λευκὸν μὲν καὶ μέλαν ὄψις, γλυκὺ δὲ καὶ πικρὸν γεῦσις· ὁμοίως δ’ ἔχει τοῦτο καὶ ἐπὶ τῶν ἄλλων. ἐπεὶ δὲ καὶ τὸ λευκὸν καὶ τὸ γλυκὺ καὶ ἕκαστον τῶν αἰσθητῶν πρὸς ἕκαστον κρίνομεν, τινὶ καὶ αἰσθανόμεθα ὅτι διαφέρει.

(An. 3.2, 426b8–14)

Aristotle’s phrasing here is, admittedly, somewhat ambiguous. Elsewhere in the De Anima he speaks, for instance, of black and white both as διαφοραί of colour and as διαφοραί of visible bodies.Footnote 111 These are, then, two candidates for the intended ‘underlying perceptual object’ in our passage. Given that the two remaining passages in the De Anima using this latter expression refer unambiguously to the quality rather than the body,Footnote 112 it seems safer to assume that this is also what Aristotle has in mind here. In any case, the term διαφορά does not refer to a difference between two qualities; rather, it refers to what is specific about one quality in contrast to the other qualities of the same kind.Footnote 113 The only alleged source of support for the three-place model in the quoted passage thus can be taken to be found in Aristotle’s description of sight as ‘[discriminating] white and black’ and of taste as ‘[discriminating] sweet and bitter’. It has been argued that what Aristotle has in mind here are cases of discriminating the actively perceived white colour from the actively perceived black colour, and so on.Footnote 114 However, there is hardly any support for this reading, which would be very difficult to reconcile with the preceding passages on κρίνειν (as we have seen). Rather, even the present passage suggests that Aristotle has something else in mind. First, it would be prima facie awkward if he was claiming that we can discriminate sweetness only from an actively perceived bitterness, implying that no simple perception of sweetness was possible but that our experience is always literally bittersweet.Footnote 115 Furthermore, the μέν … δέ structure of the quoted passage suggests that Aristotle intends to consider the discrimination of multiple qualities in relation to each other (implying a perception of their difference) separately from the basic case of discrimination, which is taken for granted as something that has already been analysed before.Footnote 116

The key meaning of κρίνειν in the basic account, as I have argued, was that of singling out or identifying the quality of the given range possessed by the perceptual object acting on the perceiver – that is, deciding, with the ultimate authority, what the perceived object is like, not for the perceiver, but on its own.Footnote 117 This has nothing to do with distinguishing two perceived qualities from each other. Rather, we should think of contexts like the wind passage from the Theaetetus.Footnote 118 There may arise disagreements about what some perceptual object is like (what colour it has, whether it is cold or warm, and so on), where the question becomes what authority we should call on. Aristotle’s emphatic answer is that the ultimate, objective, and impartial authority with regard to modal-specific aspects of perceptual objects is the perceptive organ in a healthy condition.Footnote 119

In An. 2.11, Aristotle seems to come closest to explaining how this authority is grounded and how it is exercised. In the following chapter, we shall explore the loose ends of this account and ask how it builds up to Aristotle’s second general account of perception in An. 2.12.

Footnotes

2 Bonitz Reference Bonitz1870: 409.

3 Ebert Reference Ebert1983: 185–7.

4 Ebert Reference Ebert1983: 187–9.

5 Ebert Reference Ebert1983, 189–90. Ebert goes far beyond Bonitz’s distinction in contrasting the ‘primary sense’ of κρίνειν and the meanings that are dependent on the judicial sense.

6 Ebert Reference Ebert1983, 190–5 (see p. 193 for the quotation).

7 For explicit discussions, see de Haas Reference de Haas and Salles2005: 326–8 and Perälä Reference Perälä2018; cf. e.g. Bernard Reference Bernard1988: 268, Sorabji Reference Sorabji1993: 35–6, or Polansky Reference Polansky2007: 255–6.

8 See Corcilius Reference Corcilius, Silva and Yrjönsuuri2014: 39–40. For a much milder reservation, see Caston forthcoming: Footnote n. 72, who expresses doubts about the idea that perceptual discrimination is always a discrimination of two things from each other. Cf. also Perälä Reference Perälä2018: 261, who accepts the triadic structure of discrimination, but suspends judgement on whether all cases of αἰσθάνεσθαι are discriminations.

9 For an overview, see McConkie and Loschky Reference McConkie, Loschky and Nadel2003 or O’Regan Reference O’Regan and Nadel2003. For the philosophical relevance of this phenomenon, see O’Regan and Noë Reference O’Regan and Noë2001.

10 See e.g. Beekes Reference Beekes2009: 780–1; cf. Kahn Reference Kahn2003: 381–3.

11 Kahn Reference Kahn2003: 383.

12 Ebert Reference Ebert1983: 195–8 (for the quotation, see p. 196).

13 Ebert Reference Ebert1983: 197.

14 Ebert Reference Ebert1983: 189–90 (the only other exception in the De Anima being allegedly at 1.2, 405b8, which has nothing to do with the nature of perception); cf. de Haas Reference de Haas and Salles2005: 331.

15 As the passage was commonly translated before Ebert’s work, see e.g. Hicks Reference Hicks1907 and Ross Reference Ross1961: 238 (‘judges of’), Hamlyn Reference Hamlyn1993 (‘judges about’); cf. Jannone and Barbotin Reference Jannone and Barbotin1966 (‘juge-t-il de’).

16 Cf. Reeve Reference Reeve2017 (‘discerning about these’), Polansky Reference Polansky2007: 251, Miller Reference Miller2018 (‘discriminates concerning these’), or Corcilius Reference Corcilius2017 (‘unterscheidet … betreffs dieser’).

17 Cf. Wallace Reference Wallace1882, Rodier Reference Rodier1900 (‘discerne [correctement] ses sensibles’), Smith Reference Smith1931 (‘which it discerns’), and Shields Reference Shields2016 (‘discerns these’).

18 See e.g. Pol. 3.16, 1287b15–18; cf. 3.15, 1286a27–9.

19 See e.g. Pol. 3.16, 1287b23–5; cf. 3.11, 1282a18; 4.4, 1291a39–40; 4.14, 1298a30–1; 4.15, 1299a25–7, 1300b38–40; 7.4, 1326b12–18; 7.9, 1329a3–6.

20 Protr. 60.1–2 (which is cited neither by Bonitz nor by Ebert).

21 See e.g. Pol. 4.15, 1300b38–1301a1.

22 Cf. e.g. Soph. Ref. 25, 180b26–7.

23 Ebert Reference Ebert1983: 190.

24 One reason Ebert Reference Ebert1983: 190 gives (cf. de Haas Reference de Haas and Salles2005: 331) for taking the occurrence of κρίνειν in An. 2.6 to be peculiar and not directly relevant to the core account of perceptual discrimination is that he believes it applies only to ‘special sense objects’, whereas in the case of ‘the common sensibles … it is always possible to appeal to another sense against the verdict of the first’. This argument is based on Ebert’s assumption that the basic account of perceptual κρίνειν must apply to all three kinds of perceptual contents as distinguished in An. 2.6 (see Ebert Reference Ebert1983: 195–6; cf. de Haas Reference de Haas and Salles2005: 336, Perälä Reference Perälä2018: 265, or Charles Reference Charles, Guyomarc’h, Louguet and Murgier2020: 22–3 et passim). It is telling, however, that there is no single passage in An. in which Aristotle would actually apply κρίνειν to common or coincidental objects.

25 There are two other passages in Book 1 (An. 1.2, 404b21–7 and 405b8) employing κρίνειν or its derivatives (the second of which is identified by Ebert as the only other judicial ‘exception’). However, neither of them is directly relevant to our question: the first passage seems to be only reporting a Platonist διαίρεσις (cf. An. 3.3, 428a3–5), while the second does not concern perception at all.

26 See the very first sentence introducing Empedocles’ doctrine at Sens. 7, 500.19–23, which is restated for criticism at Sens. 15, 503.25–9; cf. 19, 504.26–7; 20, 505.4–5. See also Sens. 25, 506.23–8 on Alcmaeon and 45, 512.7–10 on Diogenes. Quite a different account of perceptual κρίνειν is ascribed to Anaxagoras; see Sens. 28, 507.14–19; 33, 508.24–7; 34, 509.3–4.

27 Democritus probably called both the senses and νοῦς κανόνες in his eponymous work, cf. Sextus, M 7.138–9 (cf. Lee Reference Lee2005: 229–33); for a similar use of κανών, see Aristophanes, Birds 1001–9. For Aristotle, κανών sometimes becomes virtually synonymous with μέτρον; see e.g. EN 3.4, 1113a31–3.

28 Cf. Metaph. A.1, 981b10–13. Cf. also Aristotle’s objectivist proto-version of the Knowledge Argument at Phys. 2.1, 193a7–9.

29 For references, see Footnote n. 26.

30 See especially Sens. 28, 507.14–21. For a sceptical interpretation of Anaxagoras, see Sextus, M 7.90 (i.e. B 21); cf. Aëtius 4.9.1 (i.e. A 96), Sextus, PH 1.33.2–6 (i.e. A 97/1), Cicero, Academica 2.31.100 (i.e. A 97/2).

31 Complementary with the reasons spelled out in Chapter 2. This is not to say that Aristotle was not attentive to the fact that different people in different circumstances notice different things (for a systematic treatment of Aristotle’s approach to this phenomenon, see Cagnoli Fiecconi Reference Cagnoli Fiecconi2021). The point is that this is not relevant for the definition of the primary perceptual acts.

32 See An. 1.2, 405b10–23 and Sections 2.2 and 2.7 for a discussion.

33 ‘Only about the organs of hearing [does Clidemus say that] they do not κρίνειν themselves, but rather send [what they received] further to νοῦς, so he does not, like Anaxagoras, make νοῦς the principle of everything’ (Sens. 38, 510.9–11; cf. Section 2.3). Compare the Platonic contrast between perceiving by and perceiving through, as analysed by Burnyeat Reference Burnyeat1976, and Alexander’s account of perception as summed up in Section 5.3.

34 For a very different understanding of the contrast, which interprets LKL as articulating a relativist view of perception, see Kelsey Reference Kelsey, Radice and Zanata2018.

35 See e.g. Pol. 3.9, 1280a16–22 and 3.16, 1287a41–b3. On an unbiasedness/externality requirement concerning a good judge, cf. also Plato, Resp. 409b–c.

36 Cf. von Fritz Reference Fritz1946: 19: ‘when we see an angry or sad person …, we have … the impression … that there is something in us which responds to it and that … we understand the mood or the emotion of the person in its individual quality because, at least potentially, it is also in ourselves’.

37 See e.g. Herodotus, The Histories 6.86.28–9; Euripides, Medea 613; or Plato, Symp. 191d. In Aristotle, see e.g. EE 7.5, 1239b31; Pol. 3.9, 1280a36–40; GC 2.4, 331a23–36; or Meteor. 2.4, 360a21–7. For Empedocles (in the context of animal generation), see GA 1.18, 722b6–11.

38 For the distinction between ‘narrow’ and ‘broad’ Protagoreanism, see Fine Reference Fine1994: 213–14.

39 See Theaet. 160c4–d4, 161d4–7, 167a7–8, b3–4, 178b2–8.

40 Socrates refutes the pretension of the measure doctrine to provide a universal account of knowledge (the ‘broad’ Protagoreanism), and Aristotle follows him steadfastly on this point. However, with regard to the cases of the warm or the sweet, Socrates undeniably shows much more sympathy for Protagoras (see e.g. Theaet. 171d9–e3, 179c2–7). I agree with Lee Reference Lee2005: 112–17 that the collapse of the Secret Doctrine at Theaet. 182d–183a is not intended as a decisive refutation of ‘narrow’ Protagoreanism. When Socrates finally expresses some reservations about it, this amounts to a doubt whether a notion of truth is applicable to perception at all: because perception does not concern the ‘being’ of things, it cannot, apparently, be properly speaking ‘true’ (Theaet. 186a–e, cf. Narcy Reference Narcy and Dherbey1996: 239–42, Lee Reference Lee2005: 155–7). The question of whether Plato does or does not accept something along the lines of the Protagorean account of perception is, of course, a controversial one, dividing the two influential readings of the Theaetetus that are represented by Cornford Reference Cornford1935 and Burnyeat Reference Burnyeat1990, respectively. For an alternative reading, see Sedley Reference Sedley2004, according to whom the Protagorean account is not as such accepted by Plato but is intended to ‘foreshadow’ the physical account presented at Tim. 45b–46c, 67c–68d.

41 See Metaph. Κ.6, 1062b35–1063a5 (adapting the Protagorean notions from Theaet. 178b2–8 by purging them of their relativist flavour) and Metaph. Γ.6, 1011a3–9 (where Aristotle seems to block the kind of argument from second-order κρίνειν raised against Protagoreanism at Theaet. 170d4–10; cf. Metaph. Γ.5, 1010b3–11). As Lee Reference Lee2005: 162 puts it: ‘We have here a concession and an objection. Protagoras is correct in so far as a certain kind of perception, perception of “special”, or “proper” (idion) objects, is always correct. But it doesn’t follow that all appearances are true, because appearing is not the same as perceiving.’ For μέτρον, see also Metaph. Ι.1, 1053a35–b3. For a recent discussion, see McCready-Flora Reference McCready-Flora2015.

42 See Metaph. Γ.5, 1010b11–30 as a reaction to Socrates’ argument from the future against Protagoras at Theat. 178b–179b. In the first part of this passage, Aristotle explicitly agrees with Plato’s Socrates that the case of expert knowledge refutes ‘broad’ Protagoreanism. However, in the second part, he goes far beyond anything Plato ever wrote by making a similar claim about the senses being the ultimate authority (κυρίον) when it comes, say, to what it is – and indeed what it ever will be (and always was) – for something to be sweet. Aristotle seems to be correcting Socrates’ claim here that the vine-grower is the authority with respect to ‘the future sweetness’ as Socrates maintains (Theaet. 178c9–d2; cf. 186a): what he should have said is rather that the vine-grower is the expert and authority with respect to the wine and how it acquires its qualities from the vines out of which it is produced. As far as these qualities themselves are concerned, however, there is no authority besides the healthy sense of taste. Moreover, even the vine-grower’s expert knowledge depends depends on this condition. There are good reasons to think that, at Metaph. Γ.5, 1010b11–30, Aristotle is directly reacting to Theaet. 178b–179b: there is no other passage within Metaph. Γ.5–6 or Κ.6 in which Aristotle uses the language of κυριότης and, similarly in the Theaetetus, this language is practically limited to the mentioned passage (it is used at 178c9–d2, 178d9 and 179b6–9; none of the remaining three occurrences at 161d5, 169e2, and 206b8 is directly relevant to Aristotle’s discussion in Metaph. Γ.5). The striking notion of necessity in the quoted passage from Metaph. Γ.5 seems to be responding directly to Theat. 160b5–8.

43 One could raise this objection from all sorts of positions, be it Platonic, Protagorean, Democritean, or (proto-)sceptical.

44 The same seems true of An. 2.6, 418a14–16.

45 Besides An. 2.10, 422a20–31 and 3.2, 425b20–2, see 2.9, 421b3–8; 2.11, 424a10–15; cf. 2.8, 420a15–19.

46 His claim is introduced as spelling out a specific sense of perceiving by sight (τῇ ὄψει αἰσθάνεσθαί, An. 3.2, 425b20).

47 It is also telling, then, to compare this passage with that in An. 3.2 claiming that ‘we κρίνομεν by sight also darkness’: here, the translation ‘we discriminate’ seems very natural, but the passage is making exactly the same point as the one from An. 2.10, so there is a clear continuity between the judicial ‘deciding’ on the one hand and ‘discriminating’ on the other. If that is right, then these cannot be contrasted as two different meanings of κρίνειν. Rather, it confirms the suggestion made above that judicial overtones are essential to Aristotle’s employment of κρίνειν throughout the De Anima, even in the cases where ‘discriminating’ (or ‘discerning’) is the most natural translation.

48 Cf. Theophrastus, Sens. 2, 499.9–10.

49 Aristotle mentions only hot, cold, wet, and dry and does not include hard and soft, apparently because these latter properties are emergent and do not belong to the element themselves (see Meteor. 4.4–5, 382a8–27).

50 See especially An. 3.7, 431a17–20, which insists that there is a numerically identical μεσότης for all sense modalities (more on this passage in Section 6.6).

51 For touch as a μεσότης, see also An. 3.13, 435a21–b3 and Meteor. 4.4, 382a16–20 (for a mean disposition of sight, cf. GA 5.1, 780a22–5). For more on the questions raised by the extension, see Sections 6.5 and 7.2.

52 See An. 2.9, 422a6–7; 2.10, 422a34–b5, b15–16.

53 In the rest of An. 2.5–11, Aristotle usually talks of ‘that which can perceive’ (or ‘touch’, ‘taste’, ‘smell’ …) without spelling out the respective roles of the body and the soul (cf. Sections 1.1 and 5.4).

54 See e.g. Hicks Reference Hicks1907: 414–5, Oates Reference Oates1936: 394, Corcilius Reference Corcilius, Silva and Yrjönsuuri2014: 40 (cf. Corcilius Reference Corcilius and Cohoe2022: 144), Shields Reference Shields2016: 47, 246–7, Reeve Reference Reeve2017, Perälä Reference Perälä2018: 267–8.

55 Polansky Reference Polansky2007: 333 n. 16 draws a difference between the two notions, but applies both to the perceptive capacity as well as to the perceptive organ. Hamlyn Reference Hamlyn1993: 112–13 distinguishes between the perceptive organ as ‘the mean’ and its ‘mean state’, but he takes it for granted that both terms in Aristotle’s text (μεσότης and τὸ μέσον) refer to the same thing – namely, the organ. Johansen Reference Johansen, Saunders and van Brakel2002: 180 distinguishes between ‘a mean’ and ‘what is in the middle’, but without drawing any implications from that distinction. Grasso Reference Grasso2020: 257 distinguishes between ‘a mean’ and ‘the middle’, but the difference does not seem to play any role in his interpretation. Contrast Theodore Tracy’s careful reading reported in the following footnote.

56 Cf. Tracy Reference Tracy1969: 206 (cf. 221), who spells out μεσότης in terms of ‘form disposing and activating its matter in a state of equilibrium’, and takes τὸ μέσον to refer to ‘this “middle state” or equilibrium’ of the organ that enables it to discriminate. Unfortunately, Tracy does not explain what discrimination amounts to or how it takes place (cf. Footnote n. 97).

57 Here are some parallels that highlight the contrast in functions between the abstract noun μεσότης and the corresponding adjective: ‘With regard to anger also there is an excess, a deficiency, and a mean (μεσότης). Although they can scarcely be said to have names, yet since we call the intermediate person (τὸν μέσον) good-tempered let us call the mean (τὴν μεσότητα) good temper; of the persons at the extremes let the one who exceeds be called irascible, and his vice irascibility, and the man who falls short an inirascible sort of person, and the deficiency inirascibility’ (EN 2.7, 1108a4–9, Revised Oxford Translation; cf. Pol. 4.11, 1295a35–9). ‘With regard to justice and injustice we must consider what kind of actions they are concerned with, what sort of mean (μεσότης) justice (ἡ δικαιοσύνη) is, and between what extremes that which is just (τὸ δίκαιον) is in the middle (μέσον)’ (EN 5.1, 1129a3–5, Revised Oxford Translation, modified; cf. MM 1.33.8). For an illuminating discussion of μεσότης and τὸ μέσον in the ethical context, see Brown Reference Brown and Polansky2014 (building on Brown Reference Brown1997); cf. e.g. Hardie Reference Hardie1965, Young Reference Young1996, Hursthouse Reference Hursthouse and Kraut2006, Rapp Reference Rapp and Reis2006, Fisher Reference Fisher2018.

58 Cf. Sections 3.7 and 4.6.

59 This is a classical objection against spiritualism, for which see already Sorabji Reference Sorabji, Nussbaum and Rorty1992: 214–15.

60 This seems to follow even under the homeostatic ‘organic’ reading proposed by Ducharme Reference Ducharme2014, who maintains that perception consists in literal form replication, albeit just temporary because the organs ‘strive’ to return to their neutral state. Cf. already Tracy Reference Tracy1969: 200–22.

61 Cf. Price Reference Price1996: 289, Magee Reference Magee2000: 319, and Grasso Reference Grasso2020: 259–61.

62 Whether this is to be understood literally or analogically.

63 As noted in Section 4.4, one puzzling aspect of An. 2.10 is that, throughout the chapter, Aristotle speaks as if the tongue were the proper organ of taste, rather than a part of its medium, as he argues in An. 2.11. However, for our purposes, we can ignore this apparent inconsistency. What matters is the way in which Aristotle applies the assimilation model to the tongue here, as an example of a perceptive organ.

64 See e.g. Hicks Reference Hicks1907 (‘without losing its nature’) or Jannone and Barbotin Reference Jannone and Barbotin1966 (‘en gardant son intégrité’); cf. Themistius, In An. 71.35–6 and Philoponus, In An. 405.18–21.

65 Cf. Grasso Reference Grasso2020: 268–9.

66 For the idea that the present passage draws on the notion of preservative πάσχειν from An. 2.5, see e.g. Polansky Reference Polansky2007: 318–19 and Grasso Reference Grasso2020: 269.

67 If this suggestion is on the right track, then the notion of capacity employed in (i) is worthy of a special attention: it seems that the capacity involved here cannot be interpreted either as simply a capacity for being materially assimilated (in the literal or analogical way), or as simply a capacity for being phenomenally assimilated. Instead, it appears to essentially involve both of these aspects in a way that is yet to be determined.

68 Or, perhaps each kind of touch – for, unlike other senses, touch is of more than one range of qualities (cf. An. 2.11, 422b23–7).

69 It should also be noted that this is not a very natural reading, either, given that μεσότης did not figure in the main sentence but in a subordinate absolute genitive construction.

70 The switch from the first-person plural to the impersonal third-person singular is stylistically awkward but is certainly not unique in Aristotle’s work. For another example we need to wait less than two Bekker pages: ‘Since we perceive (αἰσθανόμεθα) that we are seeing (ὅτι ὁρῶμεν) …, it is necessary to perceive (ἀνάγκη αἰσθάνεσθαι) that one is seeing (ὅτι ὁρᾷ) either … or …’ (An. 3.2, 425b12–13).

71 The same can also be said, in a secondary manner, about the perceiver who possesses the organ.

72 See Section 5.2. This is not to say that Aristotle is always so cautious. See e.g. An. 3.3, 427a20–1 where the soul is said to discriminate something in both perception and thought. In passages like these, I take it, Aristotle expects us to apply the lesson of the ‘Rylean passage’ on our own.

73 See Grasso Reference Grasso2020: 261–4 for a critical overview of other existing interpretations.

76 Cf. Corcilius and Gregoric Reference Corcilius and Gregoric2013: 54–78. However, see Gregoric forthcoming for a non-literal understanding of Aristotle’s analogy between the perceptive soul and a point at An. 3.2, 427a9–14.

78 Corcilius Reference Corcilius, Silva and Yrjönsuuri2014: 42; see also de Haas Reference de Haas and Salles2005: 335–6 for the idea that what is ‘compared’ is the incoming sensible form and the mean; cf. Polansky Reference Polansky2007: 255–6.

79 See most clearly Grasso Reference Grasso2020: 272, cf. 267.

80 This is also the view of Ducharme Reference Ducharme2014.

81 For the different meanings of αἴσθησις, see Section 7.4.

82 In fact, Grasso himself renders αἴσθησις in our passage as ‘the sense’, and he seems to understand it in terms of the perceptive capacity rather than the organ, see Grasso Reference Grasso2020: 257 n. 1 (cf. 261 Footnote n. 12).

83 Neither Aristotle’s adoption of the Platonic catchphrase ‘up until the soul’ in An. 1.4, nor his comparison with a geometrical point at An. 3.2 427a9–14 is sufficient to commit him to this view. One can have a strongly cardio-centric reading of Aristotle (as, for example, Alexander of Aphrodisias does) and still insist that the soul is present in the heart in a very different way: for example, as Alexander says (cf. Section 5.3), by being indivisibly present throughout the whole organ (presumably this was also the way in which Alexander read MA 9 and 11, 703b26–35).

84 See An. 1.3, 406a12–22 (cf. Ferro Reference Ferro2022: 96).

85 Phys. 5.3, 226b21–3.

86 GC 1.6, 323a28–33.

87 Neither the example in GC 1.6 nor anything in the De Anima suggests this.

88 As support for the claim that Aristotle assumes non-metaphorical contact and juxtaposition between the perceptive soul and the incoming motions, Corcilius Reference Corcilius, Silva and Yrjönsuuri2014: 46–7 cites Phys. 7.2, 244b2–245a11, where Aristotle says that the perceptual qualities, such as flavours, are adjacent (ἅμα) to the senses, such as γεῦσις. But the passage is not without ambiguities, and Aristotle may well want to say nothing more than that the flavoured body must be in contact with the body of the perceiver, so that coincidentally the quality of the former and the capacity of the latter are also ‘adjacent’ (because the bodies in which they exist are adjacent in their own right). Aristotle also says here that colours are adjacent to light and that light is adjacent to sight. However, given Aristotle’s theory of light as a disposition (ἕξις) or fulfilment (ἐντελέχεια) of the transparent medium developed in An. 2.7 (and Sens. 3), it seems impossible that by ‘being ἅμα’ he means a literal non-coincidental spatial contiguity. It is clear that light is not in a place (and that it does not have a position) in its own right – but only coincidentally on account of being a disposition/fulfilment of the illuminated air that is itself in a place. If we do not assume that Aristotle adopts an entirely different theory of light in Phys. 7 than he does in An. and Sens., it is difficult to see how the passage in Phys. 7.2 could imply that sight is non-coincidentally in a place or has a position. If, instead, we do assume that there are two different theories of light presupposed in An. and Phys. 7, then it is not clear why we should take Phys. 7 to be helpful for interpreting An.’s account of perception. Another reason for caution is Aristotle’s adoption of the Platonic Formula in Phys. 7.2–3 (248a6–9; cf. Section 5.1), which goes beyond anything that he accepts in An. (the passages that might suggest the opposite – some of which are quoted by Corcilius Reference Corcilius, Silva and Yrjönsuuri2014: 47 n. 42 – are discussed in Sections 7.4 and 7.5 and in the Appendix).

89 If we imagine all colours as having values between x (corresponding to black) and y (corresponding to white), all of which are ‘measured’ by white (cf. Metaph. Ι.2, 1053b29–34), the mean in question can hardly be the geometrical, the arithmetical, or the harmonic mean (it is neither the grey nor the sallow, cf. Cat. 10, 12a18–20; nor is it the purple or the red, identified, apparently, as corresponding to the fifth and the fourth among colours at Sens. 3, 439b25–440a6). Rather, as Johansen Reference Johansen, Saunders and van Brakel2002: 181 puts it, the mean is ‘the point at which the two extremes cancel each other out’. In this sense, a certain temperature, for instance, can serve as the mean for touch (almost) as well as transparency does for sight.

90 An. 2.12, 424a32–b3. For a discussion of this passage and the notion of receiving forms without the matter, see Section 7.4. Cf. An. 3.13, 435a19–b4; for homeostatic readings of this passage, see Murphy Reference Murphy2005: 333–8 and Grasso Reference Grasso2020: 278–80.

91 In terms of the mean, Aristotle also describes a more general homeostatic mechanism possessed by animals; see e.g. PA 2.7, 652b7–27; GC 2.7, 334b15–29; cf. Meteor. 3.1 (cf. PA 3.4, 666b20–667a4; HA 1.17, 496a4–27; 3.3, 513a27–b1; and Somn. 2, 458a10–19, where the principle of the mean leads Aristotle to infer that the middle ventricle of the heart serves as the centre and origin of the self-preservative and perceptual activity of animals; cf. also Iuv. 1, 467b25–468a4). For further analysis, see Tracy Reference Tracy1969: 178–200 and King Reference King2001: 74–129, who focuses on Long., Iuv., and Resp. (cf. Terzis Reference Terzis1995, who claims to reconstruct the role of homeostasis in Aristotle’s account of emotions).

92 This idea turns out largely to agree with Grasso Reference Grasso2020, with the main difference being whether μεσότης is to be understood as referring to (a) the neutral state of the organ resulting from the counterbalancing reaction, or to (b) the perceptive capacity as the principle responsible for this counterbalancing. The latter seems to be further supported by the closeness of μεσότης at An. 2.12, 424a32–b3 to ‘the principle capable of receiving forms of the perceptual objects’.

93 We can surely perceive more than one quality of the same range by a single organ at a given time. This does not conflict with the proposed account. We need only to realize that the organ (unlike the soul) is a spatially extended entity that can ‘come to be the other extreme’ with respect to a plurality of qualities in spatially differentiated parts of it. Cf. Alexander’s view that the perceptive soul is indivisibly present throughout the perceptive organ (Section 5.3). This is not to say that the case of simultaneous perception of homogeneous qualities is a trivial matter for Aristotle. For a discussion of some of the issues involved in it, see Gregoric Reference Gregoric2007: 141–4.

94 Contrast Johansen Reference Johansen, Saunders and van Brakel2002: 181, who takes An. 2.11, 423b31–424a10 to describe ‘the manner in which the sense faculty deviates from its mean when it is affected’.

95 See Section 3.7. The perceptive capacity seems, thus, to have the role of ‘that which brings about standstill’ (τὸ στατικόν, Metaph. Δ.12, 1019a34–5).

96 For the close relation between measuring (μετρεῖν) and discrimination (κρίνειν), see the Protagorean background sketched out in Section 6.2.

97 I owe the comparison to Stephen Menn. The same model of κρίνειν is, in connection with the Peripatetics but in a different way, applied by Sextus, M 7.226 (the senses, here, function as a balance scale for νοῦς). The simile is also employed by Tracy Reference Tracy1969: 207, but it is not quite clear how it is supposed to work on his model where the organs come to acquire a quality of their own for the duration of perceiving: if there is any ‘weighing’ going on, it is only when the object ceases to act on the organ (and the organ returns to its equilibrium), which would, absurdly, imply that while I am observing x I do not discriminate x, and that discrimination of x takes place only once I stop observing x. The comparison is also used by Bradshaw Reference Bradshaw1997: 155, but in a way that openly compromises the impassivity of the soul. It is also used, in a very different way, by Johansen Reference Johansen2012b: 84.

98 See An. 2.4, 416b20–3. Cf. An. 1.3, 406a3–4 for Aristotle’s conviction that the notion of an unmoved mover has already been established elsewhere, and so can be taken for granted.

99 Cf. Menn Reference Menn2002: 130, who refers to Plato’s account of μετρητικὴ τέχνη at Prot. 356d–e. The question is (a) how exactly such a measuring art relates to the productive arts, and (b) in precisely what way it provides a model for the involvement of the perceptive soul.

100 Cf. Section 5.5.

101 This model clearly needs to be adapted if we are not to lose sight of the essential passivity of perception, which sharply distinguishes it from nutrition.

102 Tangible qualities represent a partial exception to this rule, because no body can be entirely neutral with respect to them. However, the existence of a blind spot changes nothing about the main principle (see Section 6.6).

103 See Metaph. Δ.15, 1020b30–1021a14 for the former and Metaph. Ι.1, 1053a30–b3 with Ι.6, 1057a9–12 for the latter. Prima facie, the two accounts appear to be incompatible, as observed by Menn forthcoming a: Appendix to Iγ2a (cf. Broackes Reference Broackes1999: 99–100). The former employs a notion of measure as related per se to the thing measured (‘the thing measured will remain unchanged in itself if we measure it in spans instead of cubits, unlike Protagorean sense-objects, which alter when they are “measured” by a new perceiver’), whereas the latter employs a notion of measure as that to which the thing measured is related per se (‘being in conformity or not with that standard (e.g. being equal or unequal to the appropriate length for that kind of thing, or lying flat against a straightedge or curving away from it) is an intrinsic attribute of the thing measured, while for the standard to be “in conformity” or not with the thing is not an intrinsic attribute of the standard’). The co-existence of both accounts in the Metaphysics is puzzling, not least because each seems to contain a counterargument to the other. However, the passage in Metaph. Ι.1 is actually moving from one account to the other, which suggests that the tension was not unnoticed and that, instead, Aristotle took the two accounts to be, ultimately, compatible.

104 See An. 3.2, 426b18–19, 20, 21.

105 An. 3.7, 431a19–20 (καὶ μία μεσότης, τὸ δ’ εἶναι αὐτῇ πλείω); cf. An. 3.1, 425a30–b2; Sens. 7, 449a5–13.

106 Cf. An. 3.7, 431a10–11, which defines the experience of pleasure and pain as ‘being active in virtue of the perceptive mean (τὸ ἐνεργεῖν τῇ αἰσθητικῇ μεσότητι) with respect to what is good and bad as such’.

107 When I discriminate the darkness of the air outside it is exactly because no countervailing reaction takes place in the visual modality, while I am affected by the air and countervail its agency under a different modality, and so am in a constant perceptual engagement with it which allows me to distinguish its visual quality from all potential colours (as well as intense light).

108 For the case of ‘excesses’ that are ‘destructive’ and the way in which they are discriminated, see Section 7.3.

109 Most of us, needless to say, would experience this, subjectively, as a pretty hot day. However, this evaluation may have nothing to do with the objective status of discrimination; it may simply be the result of the fact that we are used to constantly countervailing the cooling agency of the outside air (of a certain intensity). Accordingly, if there is nothing or very little to countervail, we feel hot (presumably because we miss the usual opportunity for getting rid of some of our inner heat), but that subjective feeling should be distinguished from perceptual discrimination itself: even when I feel pretty hot, I am still able to appreciate the fact that the outside air is somewhat cooler than my body.

110 One might insist that the meaning of ‘by touch’ cannot be exactly the same in the case of the tangible humidity and the case of the non-tangible lukewarmness: the former is discriminated by touch itself, whereas the latter is discriminated by touch in virtue of its integration with the other senses. The point is that this contrast does not, by Aristotle’s lights, turn the latter into a common or coincidental perceptual object: it is still discriminated by touch. ‘Privative’ objects, like intangible temperature or darkness, seem to be special cases of exclusive objects (ἴδια). Another question is whether discrimination of these objects can be analysed into an awareness of the inactivity of the respective sense plus an assurance that this inactivity is not caused by some harm on the side of the perceiver (for such an analysis, see Gregoric Reference Gregoric, Gregoric and Fink2021: 123–8). I don’t see much evidence that Aristotle was attracted by this kind of analysis (he never mentions any reflexive awareness of inactivity being involved). I am more inclined to think that, for him, this discrimination is an activity of the respective sense (albeit an activity performed in virtue of its integration with the other senses) of which we are reflexively aware just as we are aware of the standard cases of modal-specific perceptual acts.

111 For the first usage of διαφορά, see An. 2.9, 421a13; 2.10, 422b14; 2.11, 422b31–2; cf. An. 2.6, 418a13–14. For the second usage, see An. 2.8, 420a26–7; 2.11, 423b27–9, 424a12–15; cf. 3.13, 435a21–4.

112 An. 2.11, 422b32–4; 3.2, 425b13–15.

113 Much in the same way that the differentia in a canonical definition does not refer to a difference between two entities but rather to the feature that distinguishes the definiendum from other objects of the same genus. This fact is acknowledged by Perälä Reference Perälä2018: 262–3.

114 Perälä Reference Perälä2018: 263.

115 Against this, see e.g. Metaph. Γ.5, 1010b23–6 (quoted in Section 6.2).

116 Cf. An. 3.7, 431a17–22. Cf. also An. 3.3, 427a20–1 where the object of discrimination, in both perception and thinking, is described in the singular as ‘one of the beings’ (τι τῶν ὄντων).

117 This will arguably hold, mutatis mutandis, for thinking (for a characterization of thinking as a case of κρίνειν, see An. 3.3, 427a20–1 and 3.9, 432a15–18). In the only passage that explicitly discusses thinking as a case of κρίνειν – namely, An. 3.4, 429b10–22 – the question is not how we discriminate the essence of flesh from flesh, for instance (as assumed by some ancient commentators, starting with Themistius, In An. 96.8–21; cf. e.g. Perälä Reference Perälä2018: 289–90 n. 70). Rather, the question is what has the authority to identify flesh (as distinct from bone and sinew), and what has the authority to identify the unique essence of flesh.

118 Theaet. 152b–c.

119 Cf. GA 5.2, 781a18–20. It is telling that there is no single passage in the De Anima where Aristotle would talk about ‘discrimination’ of common or coincidental objects (cf. Footnote n. 24). This fact confirms the observation that the notion of perceptual κρίνειν remains here closely bound to Aristotle’s infallibility thesis, as it was first introduced at An. 2.6, 418a14–16. The only two passages in the De Anima where κρίνειν is used as potentially fallible are An. 1.2, 404b21–7, where Aristotle seems to be reporting a Platonist διαίρεσις, and An. 3.3, 428a1–5, where this διαίρεσις is recalled. I am, of course, not saying that Aristotle ascribed this narrow meaning to the verb κρίνειν as such. There is plenty of evidence to the contrary. See e.g. Insomn. 2, 460b22 where the verb is used to express a potentially false judgement on the side of the perceiver, and Mem. 2, 452b8, which talks about estimating the length of time. Moreover, for our purposes, a relatively weak interpretation of Aristotle’s infallibility thesis is entirely sufficient (see An. 3.3, 428b18–19 for a qualification on Aristotle’s part; cf. Meteor. 3.4, 375a22–8): it is sufficient for the notion of κρίνειν to work as proposed if we assume with Aristotle that the modal-specific objects are correctly perceived in normal circumstances, and, so, are correctly perceived for the most part. This qualification takes nothing away from the senses being the ultimate authorities in their domain (artisans, too, are sometimes hindered by circumstances that prevent them from properly actualizing their art, without this in any way undermining their status as the ultimate authorities in their respective domains).

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×