Hostname: page-component-669899f699-g7b4s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-04-26T22:02:21.794Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Anti-Theists cannot have Theistic Faith

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 April 2025

Elizabeth Grace Jackson*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Saint Louis University, St. Louis, MO, USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

A topic of recent interest involves the nature of theistic faith, and in particular, the boundaries of such faith. For example, philosophers have taken opposing positions on whether atheists and agnostics can have theistic faith. I consider a related question: whether anti-theists, who think God’s existence would be a bad thing, can have faith. I argue for a negative answer, although with several caveats.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Inc

1. Introduction

Much recent work in the philosophy of religion on faith: its nature, value, and rationality. Specifically, much ink has been spilled on the relationship between faith and belief: can you have faith that p if you withhold belief on p? What if you disbelieve p? While many are sympathetic to the idea that faith is consistent with withholding belief, only a few have defended the view that faith is consistent with disbelief.Footnote 1 At the same time, while it’s widely held that faith involves a desire or pro-attitude, less attention has been paid to the boundaries of faith when it comes to desire.

This issue is connected to separate literature in the philosophy of religion: the axiology of theism. The axiology of theism concerns the question of whether God’s existence would be a good thing. Pro-theists say yes, and anti-theists say no. Despite the recent attention that both faith and the axiology of theism have received in philosophy of religion circles, there has been little work bringing the two together. This is a shame, as they bear on each other in many interesting ways. While there are multiple features of the connection worth pursuing, I’ll focus here on one stark result: most anti-theists cannot have theistic faith.

There are two reasons this is significant. First, it tells us about the nature and boundaries of faith, specifically theistic faith. Whether and when theistic faith is (im)possible is important for many reasons, including the centrality of faith to many religious traditions. Faith is a theological virtue and a key aspect, if not the most central aspect, of religious commitment.Footnote 2 Second, as noted previously, this paper will highlight connections between faith and the axiology of theism, which are noteworthy yet have gone unnoticed. In contemporary work on faith, the conative aspect of religious commitment is underexplored (consider the amount of work in the philosophy of religion on topics such as the rationality of religious belief or faith’s resilience in light of counterevidence). This paper aims to fill this lacuna and spark an ongoing conversation between questions about the axiology of God and questions about the nature and rationality of faith, especially concerning faith’s conative or desire-like component.

This paper proceeds as follows. In Section 2, I provide some relevant background on both the axiology of theism (Section 2.1) and the nature of faith (Section 2.2). In Section 3, I argue for a neglected point: there’s a serious tension between theistic faith and anti-theism. Most anti-theists cannot have theistic faith. I conclude in Section 4.

2. Background

2.1. The axiology of theism

Philosophy of religion questions often fall into three general (but non-exhaustive) categories. The first, the ontology of theism, involves the question of whether God exists. The second, the epistemology of theism, involves the question of whether we should believe in God. The third, the axiology of theism, involves the question of whether we should want God to exist. You can mix and match these views; for example, you could be a theist who thinks we should not believe in God or want God to exist; on the other hand, you could be an atheist who nonetheless holds that we should believe in God and want God to exist.Footnote 3 You could also maintain that we should not want God to exist, but we should believe that God exists (or vice versa).

Many philosophers of religion have paid more attention to the ontological and epistemological questions. Less has been done on the axiological question, although there’s been a recent renewed interest in it.Footnote 4 Kahane (Reference Kahane2011) kicked off much of the contemporary literature on the axiology of theism. There, he explains what exactly the axiological question is asking:

We are not asking theists to conceive of God’s death—to imagine that God stopped existing. And given that theists believe that God created the universe, when we ask them to consider His inexistence, we are not asking them to conceive an empty void… I will understand the comparison to involve the actual world and the closest possible world where (God does [not] exist)

(676, brackets mine).

Then, to answer the axiological question, atheists should compare our world to the closest possible world in which God exists, and theists should compare our world to the closest possible world in which God does not exist. If we interpret “possible” as metaphysical possibility, however, this comparison is odd, as it’s widely thought that if (a)theism is true, it’s necessarily true. Then, the relevant value comparisons would require us to consider conditionals with necessarily false antecedents, which, on the standard Lewis-Stalnaker semantics, would all be trivially true.Footnote 5 To avoid this, many in the axiology of theism literature take the comparisons to instead involve epistemic possibility (that is, possibility given what we know). Thus, we’d compare our world to the closest epistemically possible world where (a)theism is true. In doing so, we can legitimately compare theistic and atheistic worlds (see Lougheed, Reference Lougheed2020a: 8–17 for more on this problem and some other solutions).

There are two main views in the axiology of theism. Pro-theists maintain that it would be better if God existed (than if God did not exist); we should prefer theism to atheism. Pro-theists argue that if God exists, no evil (or much less evil) is gratuitous, there is ultimate cosmic justice, God may intervene in the world to help people, and the like.Footnote 6

In contrast, anti-theists maintain that it would be better if God did not exist (than if God existed); we should prefer atheism to theism. Anti-theists argue that God’s existence compromises our privacy (Kahane, Reference Kahane2011) and undermines our autonomy (Lougheed, Reference Lougheed2019). Furthermore, several anti-theists have argued that some people’s lives would be meaningless and absurd if God existed, especially those with projects and plans intimately connected to atheism.Footnote 7

Pro- and anti-theism are not exhaustive. Neutralism is the view that God’s existence makes no axiological difference; quietism is the view that the relevant value facts are undetermined or unknowable (see Kraay & Dragos, Reference Kraay and Dragos2013 and Kraay, Reference Kraay2021 for more on these views, and a larger taxonomy of views in the axiology of theism). This paper, however, focuses on anti-theism.

Even with this restricted focus on anti-theism, two more distinctions will be useful later. The first distinction is between narrow and wide anti-theism (see Kraay, Reference Kraay2021: 5). On narrow anti-theism, God’s existence makes things worse in some respects but not overall. For example, if God’s existence makes us less autonomous, there is an associated value cost, but suppose that God also guarantees cosmic justice and ensures there is no gratuitous evil. Assuming the latter outweighs the former, God might make things worse in some respects but still make things better overall. On wide anti-theism, God’s existence makes things worse overall.

The second distinction is between personal and impersonal anti-theism. Personal anti-theism is the view that God’s existence would make things worse for us. Impersonal anti-theism is the view that if God exists, the world would be worse. For example, if God existed, and God is an infinitely valuable being, this might make the world better. Nonetheless, if God undermines our autonomy and invades our privacy, theism might be bad for us.

Now, we turn to a brief overview of the nature of faith.

2.2. The nature of faith

There are many kinds of faith. Here, we’ll focus on faith as a mental state, or attitudinal faith, as opposed to faith as an action. We’ll also focus on faith that a proposition is true, or propositional faith, as opposed to faith in a person or an ideal. Finally, since we are putting faith in conversation with the axiology of theism, our primary focus will be on religious faith, and more specifically, theistic faith, that is, faith that God exists.Footnote 8

To shed light on the nature of faith, consider the difference between two kinds of mental states. Cognitive or epistemic states have a mind-to-world direction of fit. They aim at truth and represent the world in some way. They are normally responsive to evidence and are evaluated primarily from an epistemic point of view. Examples of cognitive mental states include beliefs, credences, and probability-beliefs.

Conative mental states, by contrast, have a world-to-mind direction of fit. They reflect one’s desires or values. They do not aim at truth in the way cognitive attitudes do and thus do not require evidence for their contents. I can desire that p, even knowing p is false—e.g., I desire that I made my flight, but I know I missed it. Examples of conative mental states include desires, pro-attitudes, and beliefs about the good.

It’s widely held that attitudinal faith involves both cognitive and conative mental states.Footnote 9 There is not a consensus on what the cognitive element of faith amounts to (but see Buchak, Reference Buchak, Abraham and Aquino2017 for a helpful overview). But one common view is that the cognitive element of faith need not be a belief per se, but could be something weaker, such as high confidence, thinking the proposition of faith is the most likely of alternatives, and the like (see Howard-Snyder, Reference Howard-Snyder2013).

That said, there’s arguably more consensus on faith’s conative element, which is more important for our purposes. Faith involves a positive conative attitude: a desire or desire-like state, approval of the object of faith, or viewing the object of faith positively in some sense.Footnote 10 For example, Alston (Reference Alston, Jordan and Howard-Snyder1996: 12) says that faith “necessarily involves some pro-attitude toward its object.” Audi (Reference Audi2011: 54) similarily says, “If I have faith that God loves human beings, I have not just a cognitive attitude (the kind that, like belief, may be called true or false), but something more: a certain positive disposition toward the state of affairs being so, that is actually obtaining.”

Note a few reasons for this consensus. First, faith’s positivity explains what separates faith from mere belief. There are lots of things we merely believe that we do not desire to be true. But when we have faith that something is true, we have a desire for the object of faith, or a pro-attitude toward it, or a positive view of it—we are “for” it in some sense. Second, paradigm cases of faith involve positivity. If I have faith that you will win your game, I want you to win the game; if I have faith that it will be sunny, I see sunny weather as positive; if I have faith that there is an afterlife, I think the afterlife would be a good thing. This view also explains why negativity precludes faith; we do not have faith that there was a global pandemic or faith that a friend will never quit smoking.

Third, faith’s positivity does not require us to accept the strong claim that faith entails a full-blown desire.Footnote 11 Instead, the view is merely that faith involves some kind of positive view of its object: for example, thinking p is the best out of the alternatives you are considering, a general approval of p, or a second-order desire for p (a desire to desire p). Or, those with faith that p may also have conflicting desires but ultimately find their desire for p slightly stronger than their desire for not-p.

The only contemporary authors that I’m aware of who deny the connection between faith and positivity are Malcolm and Scott (Reference Malcolm and Scott2021, Reference Malcolm and Scott2023). Malcolm and Scott think that faith is often positive and that many examples of faith involve desire or positivity (Malcolm & Scott, Reference Malcolm and Scott2021: 14–15). However, they deny that faith always involves positivity, and they suggest that there are cases where someone has faith that p but does not have a positive view of p. For example, they argue that you might have faith that people are predestined to hell—not because you want this to be true, but because this doctrine is a part of your religious commitment. You might find this doctrine confusing and difficult to swallow, and even hope that it’s false, but you trust that God has a plan or reason (Malcolm & Scott, Reference Malcolm and Scott2021: 18; Malcolm & Scott, Reference Malcolm and Scott2023: 144). Malcolm and Scott provide several other potential counterexamples, including someone who has faith that biblical miracles occurred but does not approve of them and someone who has faith that church teachings are based on the word of God but does not want this to be true because it would require radical personal sacrifice (Malcolm & Scott, Reference Malcolm and Scott2021: 17–18).

To defend the positivity theory, I maintain that these proposed counterexamples fall into one of two groups, following Jackson (Reference Jackson2025). Some of the persons in the counterexamples genuinely have faith, in which case they genuinely have some kind of positive conative attitude to the object of faith (even if a weak one); they are likely conflicted (e.g., they have a desire for the proposition of faith to be true but also a desire for it to be false). For example, if you have faith that God predestines people to hell, you may not want this to be true. However, you are conflicted insofar as you trust that God has a plan or good reason to allow this. Thus, you do have a positive attitude toward the proposition of faith; you have conflicting desires.

On the other hand, some of the proposed cases may not involve any kind of positive attitude toward the supposed object of faith. For this second group of cases, the people do not have faith toward the objects they do not view positively; however, they may have faith that closely related propositions are true, or faith in the person who testified the proposition, and the like. Compare: if a doctor tells me I have cancer, I do not have faith that I have cancer, but I trust the doctor and thus have faith in her and in her abilities to diagnose me. Similarly, persons in these counterexamples might have faith in God or faith in a religious leader who testifies that p, but lack faith that p. Then, while Malcolm and Scott’s arguments are clever and interesting, there are plausible ways to explain their cases so that they are not genuine counterexamples to positivity theory.Footnote 12

To sum up, it’s widely held that attitudinal, theistic faith involves a cognitive and a conative component. If I have faith that God exists, I do not think God’s existence is extremely unlikely or impossible.Footnote 13 Furthermore, I desire God to exist or view God’s existence positively. With this background in place, we’ll now turn to the relationship between anti-theism and theistic faith.

3. Why (Most) Anti-Theists cannot have Theistic Faith

This section considers the boundaries of theistic faith. While this general topic has been addressed before, it’s mostly been considered from a doxastic point of view. For example, some have argued that only those who believe that God exists can have theistic faith (Malcolm & Scott, Reference Malcolm and Scott2017, Reference Malcolm and Scott2023; Mugg, Reference Mugg2016). Others have argued that agnostics can have theistic faith but not atheists (Howard-Snyder, Reference Howard-Snyder2019; Howard-Snyder & McKaughan, Reference Howard-Snyder and McKaughan2022a). Here, we’ll consider faith’s boundaries, but instead of focusing on the doxastic, we’ll focus on the conative. What limitations does theistic faith put on what the faithful can desire? Ultimately, I’ll argue that most anti-theists cannot have theistic faith.

3.1. Varieties of anti-theism

As we saw in the last section, theistic faith involves a positive evaluation of its object. If you have faith that God exists, you view theism in a positive light. Those with theistic faith view God’s existence as a good thing, prefer or desire God to exist, and/or have a pro-attitude toward God’s existence. Thus:

Positivity requirement: If S has faith that God exists, S has an overall positive conative attitude toward God’s existence.

Note that an “overall” positive conative attitude is required, meaning that S’s general mental state must portray God’s existence positively. This is meant to rule out cases where, say, S strongly prefers God not to exist but technically has conflicting desires. A weak, clearly overridden desire will not be enough for the positivity requirement; positivity must, in some sense, be a feature of S’s general view of God’s existence.Footnote 14

Consider now anti-theism. While we saw a general overview earlier, at this point, it’s worth being more specific. In fact, there are (at least) four ways to be an anti-theist found in the literature:

Anti-theist (desire): Anti-theists desire God not to exist (Nagel, Reference Nagel1997: 130).

Anti-theist (desire-normative): Anti-theists believe that we should desire God not to exist

(Kahane, Reference Kahane2011: 679).

Anti-theist (comparative-value-belief): Anti-theists believe that things would be better if God did not exist than if God existed

(Kraay, Reference Kraay2021: 2).

Anti-theist (absolute-value-belief): Anti-theists believe that things would be bad if God existed (Lougheed, Reference Lougheed2019: sec 3).

These positions are, of course, related but distinct.Footnote 15 And it’s unclear that the literature converges on one as fundamentally characteristic of the anti-theist. For example, Nagel (Reference Nagel1997: 130), who is often attributed as an early anti-theist, says he “hopes” and does not “want” there to be a God, which most closely aligns with anti-theist (desire). Kahane (Reference Kahane2011: 679) characterizes the anti-theist as not wanting God to exist and holding that they are “justified in wanting God not to exist,” which involves both anti-theist (desire) and anti-theist (desire-normative). Kraay (Reference Kraay2021: 2) characterizes the anti-theist as anti-theist (comparative value-belief). Lougheed (Reference Lougheed2019: sec 3) says that the anti-theist “holds that it would be bad if God were to exist,” which suggests anti-theist (absolute-value-belief). Lougheed also provides examples of anti-theists who simply desire God not to exist.

Finally, consider two ways that faith and anti-theism might be in tension:

Descriptive inconsistency: The anti-theist theistic cannot have faith as a matter of descriptive, psychological fact.

Normative inconsistency: The anti-theist cannot rationally have theistic faith.Footnote 16

We’ll see that certain, robust anti-theists cannot have theistic faith, descriptively or normatively. Then, we’ll explore how weaker strands of anti-theism are consistent with theistic faith. Finally, we’ll return to strong anti-theism and consider two potential exceptions to the claim that faith and strong anti-theism are inconsistent.

3.2. (Most) Strong anti-theists cannot have theistic faith

Given these distinctions, in what sense are anti-theism and faith inconsistent? Well, first consider “strong anti-theist”: the person who is a wide anti-theist in all four senses (we’ll address narrow anti-theism in Section 3.3). The strong anti-theist desires God not to exist, affirms this desire as rational, and believes that God’s existence would make things worse in both an absolute sense and a comparative sense (that is, compared to atheism). Given the nature and scope of these attitudes, it seems irrational for the strong anti-theist to also take a general positive conative attitude toward God’s existence: they judge theism as comparatively and absolutely bad, desire God not to exist, and take this desire to be rational.

Furthermore, it also seems extremely psychologically difficult for a strong anti-theist to have faith, even if they are irrational. This person would be engaged, at best, in a serious kind of double-mindedness. While they could perhaps think there are very limited, small respects in which God’s existence would be a good thing (that is narrow pro-theism), this is insufficient for a general (that is wide) positive conative attitude toward theism, as these small benefits will likely be swamped by the other, sweeping negative value judgments they make about theism. So, strong anti-theism is normatively, and in most cases, descriptively inconsistent with having theistic faith (with an extreme kind of double-mindedness being a rare but possible exception).

This point is strengthened by considerations raised by Ballard (Reference Ballard2024). Ballard considers biblical theism in the Judeo-Christian tradition, which involves worship and devotion to God. Ballard argues that those who are biblical theists not only cannot be anti-theists but should be pro-theists. Ballard (Reference Ballard2024: 13–14) explains:

The Bible understands marriage as a picture of religious faith. The bond between one spouse and another parallels the bond between God and humanity. One aspect of this parallel is the level of devotion the bond requires. And, in marriage as in faith, that level of devotion cannot survive the thought that the beloved, whether human or divine, makes our lives worse overall.

While Ballard’s point is less about the pro-attitude required for faith and more about a biblical understanding of worshipful love, it’s instructive for our purposes. The level of devotion required for theistic faith is not consistent with viewing the object of faith negatively. Because the strong anti-theist takes a robust, intensely negative stance to theism, they cannot have theistic faith.Footnote 17 (However, as we’ll see in the next section, I do not think theistic faith requires pro-theism.)

One might wonder: should we characterize anti-theism in this strong sense, that is, as the conjunction of all four senses of anti-theism? Is this out of step with the axiology literature? I think not; those in this literature often take anti-theism to involve several, if not all, of the aforementioned categories of anti-theism. For one, as mentioned, many authors (e.g., Kahane, Lougheed) seem to understand anti-theism as a conjunction of several of the positions above. Second, there are plausible principles that connect these strands of anti-theism (e.g., principles that connect our beliefs about goodness and what we (should) desire; see e.g. Hazlett, Reference Hazlett2021; Gregory, Reference Gregory2021). Third, it seems psychologically natural that those who are anti-theists in one sense would be anti-theists in other senses (we probably endorse most of our desires as rational, otherwise, we’d give them up; our desires generally tend to correlate with our beliefs about value, etc.). For all these reasons, I do not think understanding anti-theism in the strong sense is inappropriate. And as we have seen, there’s a general incompatibility between faith and this strong anti-theism. But, as we’ll see, that does not mean that all forms of anti-theism preclude faith.

3.3. Weaker anti-theism and faith?

There are thinner versions of anti-theism that are compatible with having theistic faith. This is important because while faith that God exists has boundaries and conditions—not everyone has theistic faith—we do not want to be overly exclusive either. Setting the bar too high might exclude real and significant cases of faith. Thus, it’s worth considering forms of anti-theism that might be compatible with theistic faith.

First, and perhaps most obvious, is narrow anti-theism. Recall that the narrow anti-theist maintains that God’s existence makes the world worse in some respects, but not overall; they have a pro tanto desire for God not to exist. This desire could be relatively strong, and they could even endorse it as rational. But suppose they have conflicting desires: while it’s true they desire God not to exist, they feel conflicted, and they want God to exist on another level or for other reasons. Those with conflicting desires can still have faith if their desire for theism is stronger (even marginally stronger) than their desire for atheism. One might have just the slightest preference for theism over atheism, but this is sufficient for the positivity of faith. This anti-theist will lack the general value judgments that God’s existence is bad (or worse than God’s nonexistence), as they are merely a narrow anti-theist, but could still have a pro tanto desire for God not to exist and endorse this desire as rational.Footnote 18

Second, consider the anti-theist who desires God not to exist (the first sense of anti-theism), but, on a higher level, fails to identify with this desire. Here, there are two possibilities. The anti-theist might think their anti-theist desire is irrational. They might overall judge God’s existence to be a good thing because, say, theism would provide their life a special kind of meaning and purpose, but for some reason, they cannot shake the desire for God not to exist—perhaps they think there would be additional, difficult moral obligations on theism. But they also think this latter consideration does not rationalize their anti-theistic desire. In general, we can have desires that we do not endorse—the desire to sit around all day when deadlines are looming, the desire to get back with an abusive ex, and so forth. While these are genuine desires, insofar as we do not endorse them, we realize that their objects are not ultimately good for us. Then, an anti-theist who takes their anti-theistic desire to be irrational could possibly have theistic faith.

Note further that endorsing a desire as rational is distinct from having a second-order desire (a desire to desire something); you could endorse a desire as rational but lack the desire to have the desire. Then, a related but distinct possibility for anti-theistic faith is to have a higher-order desire for God to exist but a first-order desire for God not to exist.Footnote 19 In sum, the anti-theist with either (i) the un-endorsed desire for atheism or (ii) the mere higher-order desire for theism can both rationally and psychologically have the positive attitude required for theistic faith.

What’s more, recall the distinction between personal and impersonal anti-theism: Personal anti-theism is the view that God’s existence is worse for us. Impersonal anti-theism is the view that God’s existence makes the world worse. This distinction provides additional wiggle room in terms of the compatibility of faith and anti-theism. Consider, for example, someone who thinks God’s existence would be a bad thing for the world but a good thing for themselves: an impersonal anti-theist but a personal pro-theist. This person could nonetheless conceivably desire God to exist or at least have the relevant pro-attitudes required for faith. The personal anti-theist but impersonal pro-theist may also be able to have theistic faith. The extent to which these combinations are possible seems to depend, at least partially, on one’s background preferences. For example, consider a selfless individual who cares much more about the world than himself. Suppose he thinks God’s existence would be good for himself but bad for the world. Because the sense in which he’s a pro-theist is insignificant to him, he may be precluded from having theistic faith. But on the other hand, if he were an impersonal pro-theist but a personal anti-theist, given his background preferences, he seems like an apt candidate for theistic faith.Footnote 20

Finally, consider two reasons that those with theistic faith need not be strong, considered, or committed pro-theists. First, theistic faith seems consistent with neutralism (understood as the belief that God does not make a value difference). Plausibly, one could be a neutralist but nonetheless have a slight personal preference for theism (in the same way that one could be an agnostic but have a slightly higher credence—or subjective probability—that God exists).

Second, consider the person who has never explicitly considered the axiological question or formed any beliefs about the value of (a)theism. They could want God to exist, even without explicit beliefs about theism’s value or goodness; this stance would not preclude theistic faith. Furthermore, even if this person lacked a full-blown desire that God exists, they might have another positive stance to theism: a higher-order desire, a general approval, or something similar (see Jackson Reference Jackson2025). Then, they could still have faith, as these weaker conative attitudes are sufficient for faith’s positivity, even though they lack both explicit pro-theistic beliefs and a desire for theism.

3.4. Strong anti-theism redux

We saw in Section 3.2 that there’s a general incompatibility between strong anti-theism and faith. In this final subsection, I explore two possible exceptions to this general claim. Note that these both require certain attitudes or actions that are unlikely to be characteristic of most anti-theists, so these possibilities do not affect my ultimate conclusion that most anti-theists cannot have theistic faith.

First, suppose someone finds themselves convinced by the arguments for anti-theism. They are a strong anti-theist. However, they are unhappy about this; they grudgingly accept anti-theism. While this person is an anti-theist, perhaps even in all four senses above, they are reluctant. They wish they were not convinced by anti-theistic arguments; they wish they had better grounds to desire God to exist and/or better arguments that God’s existence would be a good thing. As a specific example, consider someone who suspects that their anti-theism brings them one step closer to abandoning their childhood faith and thus their entire way of life. While they may be a strong anti-theist, there’s still a sense in which they fail to identify with this desire (see Frankfurt Reference Frankfurt1971).Footnote 21 I’m open to the possibility that this person, and others who similarly fail to identify with their anti-theism, could have religious faith. Insofar as they regret their anti-theism, this may count as a weak but general positive conative attitude to theism. They are comparable to the faithful person with a mere higher-order desire for theism.

Second, recall that at the beginning of the paper, we restricted our focus to attitudinal faith. Faith as an attitude requires certain cognitive and conative attitudes toward its object. But consider action-focused faith: faith as an action. Plausibly, this is what we are thinking of when we say that someone takes a “leap of faith.” Action-focused faith conceivably does not require the attitudes that are necessary for attitudinal faith (Jackson, Reference Jackson2024; Speak, Reference Speak2007). Thus, strong anti-theists may be able to have action-focused theistic faith (that is, it’s psychologically possible for them to act as if theism were true), even if they in no sense desire God to exist or take theism to be a positive thing.

Could it ever be rational for a strong anti-theist to take a leap of faith? Yes, for the anti-theist who is a theist. We rationally act on p because we believe p (even though do not desire p) all the time, e.g., there’s a global pandemic, it’s raining, I missed my flight. However, a more challenging question: could the atheist anti-theist rationally take a leap of faith? That’s less clear, as on the standard models, rational action is a function of the conative and the cognitive. While, in some circumstances, just a conative attitude or just a cognitive attitude is sufficient for rational action (see Jackson, Reference Jackson2021, Reference Jackson2024), the atheist anti-theist lacks both. It’s not even clear that such a person could, say, take Pascal’s wager without some kind of general pro-theistic stance (that is acknowledging the goodness of the possibility on which God exists and they take the wager; see Jackson, Reference Jackson2023b). Then, the atheist anti-theist may need a change in mental states before they can rationally take a leap of faith.

4. Conclusion

When the axiology of theism and the faith literatures are brought together, significant insights and new areas of research are revealed. Most notably, we have seen that theistic faith is inconsistent with a strong anti-theistic stance: most strong anti-theists cannot have theistic faith. The resulting view is not overly restrictive; faith does not require explicit pro-theistic beliefs, and anti-theists of certain limited stripes can have faith. It’s also not overly inclusive, as once we consider faith’s positivity requirement, the tension is clear. One who is a strong anti-theist, in both personal and impersonal senses, with no higher-order desires for theism or other positive conative attitudes toward theism, is excluded from having attitudinal theistic faith.

Acknowledgements

Thanks to two anonymous referees at this journal for helpful feedback. Thanks also to Brian Ballard, Scott Hill, Jonathan Spates, Chris Tweedt, Sylwia Wiczewska, and Mohammad Saleh Zarepour for helpful written comments on previous drafts. Thanks to Perry Hendricks, Klaas Kraay, Kirk Lougheed, Andrew Moon, Jeff Tolly, and the audiences at the 2023 Canadian Philosophical Association, 2022 Cambridge Workshop on Islamic Epistemology, 2021 Virginia Philosophy of Religion Workshop, and the 2021 Tyndale UK Philosophy of Religion Conference for their useful comments and questions.

Elizabeth Grace Jackson is an Associate Professor of Philosophy at St. Louis University. Her research focuses on epistemology and philosophy of religion. She is currently working on a book defending epistemic permissivism.

Footnotes

1 Pojman (Reference Pojman1986), Audi (Reference Audi1991, Reference Audi2008, Reference Audi2011), Alston (Reference Alston, Jordan and Howard-Snyder1996), Speak (Reference Speak2007), Howard-Snyder (Reference Howard-Snyder2013), Howard-Snyder & McKaughan (Reference Howard-Snyder and McKaughan2022a), McKaughan & Howard-Snyder (Reference McKaughan and Howard-Snyder2022a), among others, argue that faith that p is consistent with withholding belief on p. Whitaker (Reference Whitaker2019) and Lebens (Reference Lebens2023) argue that faith that p is consistent with disbelief that p. For defenses of the claim that faith that p requires belief that p, see Mugg (Reference Mugg2016), Malcolm & Scott (Reference Malcolm and Scott2017), Scott (Reference Scott2020), and Malcolm & Scott (Reference Malcolm and Scott2023).

2 Note that it’s controversial whether, how often, and in what sense, faith is a virtue. On some of these controversies, see Audi (Reference Audi2011), Jeffrey (Reference Jeffrey2017a, Reference Jeffrey2017b), McKaughan & Howard-Snyder (Reference McKaughan and Howard-Snyder2022b), and Jackson (Reference Jackson2023a: section. 3c).

3 But for an interesting argument that theism entails pro-theism, see Ballard (Reference Ballard2024).

4 The axiology of theism was pioneered by Kahane (Reference Kahane2011). See also Kraay and Dragos (Reference Kraay and Dragos2013), Lougheed (Reference Lougheed2020a, Reference Lougheed2020b), and Kraay (Reference Kraay2018, Reference Kraay2021).

5 Thanks to an anonymous referee for encouraging me to address this.

6 See Kraay and Dragos (Reference Kraay and Dragos2013), Penner and Lougheed (Reference Penner and Lougheed2015), Penner and Arbour (Reference Penner, Arbour and Kraay2018), and Jackson (Reference Jacksonforthcoming-b) for defenses of pro-theism.

7 See Nagel (Reference Nagel1997: 130), Kahane (Reference Kahane2011, Reference Kahane and Kraay2018), and Lougheed (Reference Lougheed2017, Reference Lougheed2019, Reference Lougheed2020a) for defenses of anti-theism. For more on the ways that (a)theism interacts with life’s meaning, see Mawson (Reference Mawson2016).

8 For more on these distinctions between various kinds of faith, see Jackson (Reference Jackson2023a). For summaries of recent literature on faith, see Buchak (Reference Buchak, Abraham and Aquino2017), Rettler (Reference Rettler2018), and Jackson (Reference Jackson and Sylvanforthcoming-a).

9 Those who argue that faith involves the conative and the cognitive include Howard-Snyder (Reference Howard-Snyder2013), Page (Reference Page and Kvanvig2017), Jackson (Reference Jackson2021), (Reference Jackson, Oliveira and Silva2022a), (Reference Jackson and Lamport2022b), Howard-Snyder and McKaughan (Reference Howard-Snyder and McKaughan2022a), Howard-Snyder and McKaughan (Reference Howard-Snyder and McKaughan2022b), McKaughan and Howard-Snyder (Reference McKaughan and Howard-Snyder2022a), McKaughan and Howard-Snyder (Reference McKaughan and Howard-Snyder2022b), among many others.

10 Those who argue that faith involves desire or positivity include Alston (Reference Alston, Jordan and Howard-Snyder1996: 12), Plantinga (Reference Plantinga2000: 292), Schellenberg (Reference Schellenberg2005: 133), Audi (Reference Audi2011: 67, 79), Howard-Snyder (Reference Howard-Snyder2013: 362–363), Kvanvig (Reference Kvanvig2013: 113), Buchak (Reference Buchak, Callahan and O’Connor2014: 53), Ballard (Reference Ballard2017: 215–217), Page (Reference Page and Kvanvig2017), Jackson (Reference Jackson2021: 41), Tweedt (Reference Tweedt2023, Reference Tweedt2024) among many others. The idea that faith involves positivity (or “the will”) traces back to at least Aquinas (ST IIaIIae 2.9 ad 2; IIaIIae 4.2; cf. Stump, Reference Stump and MacDonald1991: 191). For more on Aquinas on faith, see Floyd (Reference Floyd2024). For more on the history of faith, see Swindal (Reference Swindal2024).

11 See Jackson (Reference Jackson2025). Some in the literature, such as Pojman (Reference Pojman1986: 126), appear to endorse the stronger view that faith entails desire. Others more explicitly defend pluralism concerning faith’s conative states; see Howard-Snyder and McKaughan (Reference Howard-Snyder and McKaughan2022a) and McKaughan and Howard-Snyder (Reference McKaughan and Howard-Snyder2022a).

12 Thanks to an anonymous referee for encouraging me to expand on this response to Malcolm and Scott. This response draws on a longer response to Malcolm and Scott on behalf of positivity theory from Jackson (Reference Jackson2025). See also Waggoner (Reference Waggonerforthcoming).

13 For a discussion of the possibility that faith that p might be consistent with an extremely low credence in p, see Howard-Snyder and McKaughan’s discussion of Lara Buchak’s view of faith (Howard-Snyder & McKaughan, Reference Howard-Snyder and McKaughan2022b: 317–323). For more on faith’s relationship to credence, see Jackson (Reference Jackson2019).

14 Thanks to an editor at this journal for helpful discussion.

15 As we’ll see later, any of these positions can be understood in a narrow or wide sense. Note also that the comparative/absolute distinction could be framed in terms of both values beliefs and desires (or preferences); however, those in the literature tend to frame it as value-beliefs, so I’ve followed suit, and I do not think much will hang on the desire/value belief distinction for our purposes. Thanks to Chris Tweedt and an anonymous referee for helpful discussion and clarification of the various distinctions here.

16 Where the rationality in question would be the sense in which desires can be rational or irrational (so practical rationality is a likely candidate, but there is disagreement here; see Ballard, Reference Ballard2017). Thanks to Brian Ballard and Chris Tweedt for helpful discussion on this point and the various distinctions made in Section 3.1.

17 Thanks to Brian Ballard for helpful discussion.

18 Although, as Sylwia Wilczewaska points out, it’s not clear this person is truly an anti-theist, since they are a narrow anti-theist but a wide pro-theist.

19 Thanks to an anonymous referee for pointing out that higher-order desire comes apart from endorsing a desire as rational, so there are two distinct possibilities here.

20 Thanks to an anonymous referee for this example and the insight that background preferences are relevant.

21 Thanks to Sylwia Wilczewaska, Klaas Kraay, and an anonymous referee for helpful discussion, and to an anonymous referee for this example. See Jackson (Reference Jackson2025).

References

Alston, W. (1996). Belief, acceptance, and religious faith. In Jordan, J. and Howard-Snyder, D. (Eds.), Faith, freedom, and rationality (pp. 327). Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Audi, R. (1991). Faith, belief, and rationality. Philosophical Perspectives, 5, 213239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, R. (2008). Belief, faith, and acceptance. The International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 63(1–3), 87102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, R. (2011). Rationality and religious commitment. OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ballard, B. (2017). The rationality of faith and the benefits of religion. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 81, 213227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ballard, B. (2024). The threat of anti-theism: What is at stake in the axiology of god? Philosophical Quarterly, 74(2), 408430.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchak, L. (2014). Rational faith and justified belief. In Callahan, L. F. & O’Connor, T. (Eds.), Religious faith and intellectual virtue (pp. 4973). OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchak, L. (2017). Reason and faith. In Abraham, W. J. & Aquino, F. D. (Eds.), The oxford handbook of the epistemology of theology (pp. 4663). OUP.Google Scholar
Floyd, S. (2024). Aquinas: Philosophical theology. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://iep.utm.edu/thomas-aquinas-political-theology/.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H. G. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy 68 (1):520.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gregory, A. (2021). Desire as belief: A study of desire, motivation, and rationality. OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hazlett, A. (2021). Desire and goodness. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 105(1), 160180.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howard-Snyder, D. (2013). Propositional faith: What it is and what it is not. Religious Studies, 55(4), 447468.Google Scholar
Howard-Snyder, D. (2019). Can fictionalists have faith? It all depends. American Philosophical Quarterly, 50(4), 357372.Google Scholar
Howard-Snyder, D., & McKaughan, D. J. (2022a). Faith and resilience. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 91(3), 205241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howard-Snyder, D., & McKaughan, D. J. (2022b). Theorizing about faith with Lara Buchak. Religious Studies, 59, 297326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, E. (2019). Belief, credence, and faith. Religious Studies, 55(2), 153168.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, E. (2021). Belief, faith, and hope: On the rationality of long-term commitment. Mind, 130(517), 3557.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, E. (2022a). Faith, hope, and justification. In Oliveira, L. R. G. & Silva, P. (Eds.), Propositional and doxastic justification (pp. 201216). Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, E. (2022b). Faith and reason. In Lamport, M. A. (Ed.), The handbook of philosophy of religion (pp. 167177). Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Jackson, E. (2023a). Faith: Contemporary perspectives. The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://iep.utm.edu/faith-contemporary-perspectives/Google Scholar
Jackson, E. (2023b). Faithfully taking Pascal’s Wager. The Monist, 106(1), 3545.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, E. (2024). Can atheists have faith? Philosophic Exchange, 1(1): 122.Google Scholar
Jackson, E. (2025). Faith is weakly positive. Synthese, 205(1), 119.Google Scholar
Jackson, E. (Forthcoming-a). The epistemology of faith and hope. In Sylvan, K. (Ed.), The blackwell companion to epistemology (3rd ed.). Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Jackson, E. (Forthcoming-b). The epistemic axiology of theism. Ergo.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, A. (2017a). How aristotelians can make faith a virtue. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 20, 393409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jeffrey, A. (2017b). Does hope morally vindicate faith?. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 81, 193211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahane, G. (2011). Should we want god to exist?. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 82(3), 674696.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahane, G. (2018). If there is a hole, it is not God-shaped. In Kraay, K., ed., Does God Matter? Essays on the Axiological Consequences of Theism (pp. 95131). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kraay, K. (Ed.), (2018). Does god matter? Essays on the axiological consequences of theism. Routledge.Google Scholar
Kraay, K. (2021). The axiology of theism. CUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraay, K., & Dragos, C. (2013). On preferring god’s non-existence. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 43(2) 157178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kvanvig, J. (2013). Affective theism and people of faith. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 37, 109128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lebens, S. (2023). Amen to Daat: On the foundations of Jewish epistemology. Religious Studies, 59, 465478.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lougheed, K. (2017). Anti-theism and the objective meaningful life argument. Dialogue, 56, 337355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lougheed, K. (2019). On how to (not) to argue for preferring God’s non-existence. Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review, 58(4): 677699.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lougheed, K. (2019). The axiology of theism. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://iep.utm.edu/axiology-of-theismi/Google Scholar
Lougheed, K. (2020a). The axiological status of theism and other worldviews. Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lougheed, K. (Ed.) (2020b). Four views on the axiology of theism. Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Malcolm, F., & Scott, M. (2017). Faith, belief, and fictionalism. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 98, 257274.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malcolm, F., & Scott, M. (2021). True grit and the positivity of faith. European Journal of Analytic Philosophy, 17(1), 532.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malcolm, F., & Scott, M. (2023). A philosophy of faith: Belief, truth, and varieties of commitment. Routledge.Google Scholar
Mawson, T. J. (2016). God and the meanings of life: what god could and couldn’t do to make our lives more meaningful. Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
McKaughan, D. J., & Howard-Snyder, D. (2022a). How does trust relate to faith?. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 52(4), 411427.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKaughan, D. J., & Howard-Snyder, D. (2022b). Faith and faithfulness. Faith and Philosophy, 39, 125.Google Scholar
Mugg, J. (2016). In defence of the belief-plus model of faith. The European Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 8(2), 201219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, T. (1997). The last word. OUP.Google Scholar
Page, M. (2017). The posture of faith. In Kvanvig, J. L. (Ed.), Oxford studies in philosophy of religion 8 (pp. 227244). OUP.Google Scholar
Penner, M. A., & Arbour, B. H. (2018). Arguments from evil and evidence for pro-theism. In Kraay, K. (Ed.), Does god matter? Essays on the axiological consequences of theism (pp. 192202). Routledge.Google Scholar
Penner, M. A., & Lougheed, K. (2015). Pro-theism and the added value of morally good agents. Philosophia Christi, 17, 5369.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, A. (2000). Warranted christian belief. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pojman, L. (1986). Faith without belief?. Faith and Philosophy, 3(2), 157176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rettler, B. (2018). Analysis of faith. Philosophy Compass, 13(9), 110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schellenberg, J. L. (2005). Prolegomena to a philosophy of religion. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Scott, M. (2020). Faith, fictionalism and bullshit. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy, 9(2), 94104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Speak, D. (2007). Salvation without belief. Religious Studies, 43(2), 229236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stump, E. (1991). Aquinas on faith and goodness. In MacDonald, S. (Ed.), Being and goodness: The concept of the good in metaphysics and philosophical theology (pp. 179207). Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Swindal, J. (2024). Faith: Historical perspectives. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://iep.utm.edu/faith-re/Google Scholar
Tweedt, C. (2023). The perspectival account of faith. Religious Studies, 59 4, 635650.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tweedt, C. (2024). An argument for the perspectival account of faith. Religious Studies, 60(1), 120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waggoner, M. (Forthcoming). “What’s love (and belonging) got to do with it? Negative and positive conative elements underlying gritty faith.” Faith and Philosophy.Google Scholar
Whitaker, R. K. (2019). Faith and disbelief. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 85, 149172.CrossRefGoogle Scholar