Religion and Explanation
What bearing should religious convictions have on how phenomena in nature are understood and explained?
The answer one receives to this question depends a great deal on whom one is asking. To those for whom the answer is ‘none whatsoever’, their reasons for keeping religion out of the mix often line up with one of two common ways in which religion is construed in relation to science. For holders of the first of these, known as the ‘non-overlapping magisteria’ view, religions simply are not explanatory entities. Responsibility for explaining phenomena in nature belongs to science, they say, while religion reigns over the domain of meaning. As palaeontologist Stephen Jay Gould puts it, ‘Science tries to document the factual character of the natural world, and to develop theories that coordinate and explain these facts. Religion, on the other hand, operates in the equally important, but utterly different, realm of human purposes, meanings, and values – subjects that the factual domain of science might illuminate, but can never resolve’.Footnote 1 Science alone, for followers of Gould, is responsible for explaining what happens in nature, and so religion and science do not directly compete with each other.Footnote 2
For adherents of the second view, religions are direct but deficient explanatory competitors to science.Footnote 3 Martin Kettle’s Guardian column immediately following the horrific 2004 Indian Ocean earthquake and tsunami exemplifies this competitive logic.Footnote 4 Kettle asserts the existence of two possible answers to the question of why such a catastrophic event might have occurred: ‘As with previous earthquakes, any explanation of this latest one poses us a sharp intellectual choice. Either there is an entirely natural explanation for it, or there is some other kind’. The ‘natural’ one he has in mind is the one put forward by scientists – in this case, seismologists. The ‘other kind’ refers to explanations derived from a ‘non-scientific belief system’, and whose coherence Kettle sincerely doubts. Undergirding this competitive view is the idea that scientific and religious explanations are separable according to the causes to which they appeal. Science explains what happens in nature naturalistically – that is, by appealing to natural causality – while religious persons (so the argument goes) expect supernatural causes to be present and therefore propose explanations that appeal to supernatural agencies and causes.
Despite religion’s best efforts, holders of this second view say, the historical record clearly evidences science’s explanatory superiority. Triumphalist historical narratives, such as those purveyed by evolutionary biologist Jerry Coyne, purportedly demonstrate that in episode after episode science has uncovered the correct explanation for countless phenomena that had once been explained – erroneously – by religion:
Science nibbles at religion ... relentlessly consuming divine explanations and replacing them with material ones. Evolution took a huge bite a while back, and recent work on the brain has shown no evidence for souls, spirits, or any part of our personality or behavior distinct from the lump of jelly in our head. We now know that the universe did not require a creator. Science is even studying the origin of morality.Footnote 5
History thus reveals what religions really are: failed sciences.Footnote 6 If the past is anything to go by, we can expect explanations infused with the supernatural to continue ‘retreat[ing] into the ever-shrinking gaps not yet filled by science’ until every one of them has been identified and eliminated.Footnote 7 Religions should therefore steer well clear of explanation.Footnote 8
For holders of either of these views, religious beliefs should have nothing to do with explanations of phenomena in nature, and naturalistic explanation is unimaginable as a constitutive part of a religious outlook or something that religious people might make use of. For those who see the world through religious eyes, however, neither of these approaches typically is acceptable. Many religious persons believe that their religious convictions are relevant to how they explain what happens in nature, and think that their explanations should take account of those convictions. At the same time, the historical record includes countless religious persons who have found their traditions to be hospitable (to a greater or lesser extent) to naturalistic forms of explanation.Footnote 9 In their efforts to let the full range of their commitments bear on their understanding of nature, religious persons frequently defy the clean separation of religion and science that those wanting to keep religious elements out of the study of nature seek to maintain.Footnote 10
Providential Naturalism
Among those Christians who think that their religious commitments matter to how they understand and explain phenomena in nature, one doctrinal locus that has long been thought germane to the topic is the doctrine of providence. No single view of providence has prevailed within the Christian tradition, but throughout history Christians generally have understood it to mean that God creates, upholds, and provides for the entire created order. That provision is diverse: ‘Everywhere the Bible speaks of God as one who creates, preserves, upholds, wills, acts, governs, foredains, elects, calls, predestines, judges, redeems, forgives, reconciles, provides for, protects, heals, and loves’.Footnote 11 As the early modern authors we look at in the following chapters attest, providence is especially relevant to explanations of occurrences in nature because it has a direct bearing on how Christians think about natural causality.
In recent times, Christians have often adopted one of three views of the relations between providence and natural causality. According to the first, God governs the world in such a way that natural causality can explain every single occurrence in nature. Certain Victorian-era Christians such as James Clerk Maxwell, for example, believed that God providentially governs nature, but thought that God’s provision manifests not through both natural and miraculous occurrences but through natural occurrences alone. God, Maxwell thought, governs through natural laws that are completely uniform in operation. All phenomena in nature are thus generated by the temporal unfolding of natural causality, and explanations of phenomena need appeal only to natural causes.Footnote 12
To holders of the second view, God’s providential oversight of nature means that nature possesses significant, but not total, orderliness and predictability.Footnote 13 Created entities are brought into being and sustained in their operation at all times by God, and for some percentage of all phenomena in history nature’s causal activity is sufficiently regular that it is not necessary to invoke the action of the transcendent cause (i.e., the vertical plane) that holds them in being and energises their activity when explaining their causal interactions with each other on the horizontal plane.Footnote 14 Natural causality cannot, however, account for the remaining phenomena, because those occurrences are miraculous. God’s providential guidance of the created order thus means that their explanations will at times be naturalistic, and at other times not. To assume that a naturalistic explanation can be provided for every single phenomenon in nature is to misunderstand how God works in the world.
For holders of either the first or second views, the extent to which natural causality can explain occurrences in nature flows from the underlying picture of providence. For those who subscribe to the third view, providence is bracketed out and a fully naturalistic methodology is instead embraced. Among Christian professional scientists, for example, any personal convictions they may have about providence are set aside once they walk into the laboratory and follow science’s fully naturalistic methodology. Outside the lab they might understand providence to mean that certain occurrences are miraculous and thus beyond the explanatory scope of natural causality. Inside the lab, however, they follow the norms of the scientific community and submit to its explanatory constraints, one of which is that phenomena in nature are explicable through natural causality alone. By methodologically limiting their explanations to natural causes, their beliefs about God’s providential government of the created order and the possibility of supernatural causality in history are rendered immaterial.Footnote 15
Exponents of the first and second views deploy holistic explanatory frameworks that emerge from how they understand providence. In both cases their view of nature reflects an integral approach that draws on the full range of their commitments.Footnote 16 In this book we call these integrated providence and natural causality frameworks providential naturalisms, and refer to those who employ such frameworks to understand and explain phenomena as providential naturalists. From a causal perspective, providential naturalisms constitute a spectrum of possible positions. At one end are those (like Maxwell) who adopt the first, fully naturalistic view described above. They are committed to a providential outlook, but their understanding of providence leads them to think that 100 per cent of phenomena throughout history are generated by natural causality.Footnote 17 We call those persons providential full naturalists, or full naturalists for short. For those who adopt the second view described above, the proportion of phenomena generated by natural causality is less than 100 per cent. We call them providential partial naturalists, or partial naturalists for short. Holders of the third view are already widely known as methodological naturalists.Footnote 18
These three views indicate that the relations between providence and natural causality among Christians have historically been quite varied. Behind all three, however, is the idea that one can be religious and at the same time study and explain phenomena in nature in ways that rely heavily on natural causality and naturalistic explanation. The first and second naturalism-within-religion approaches also challenge the idea that natural causality belongs solely to science, call into question any notion that religions are interested only (or even primarily) in supernatural causality, and suggest that segregating natural causality and theological convictions into separate categories like ‘science’ and ‘religion’ is not the only way to carve up the explanatory territory.Footnote 19
Providential Naturalisms in Early Modern England
For those Christians who think that the doctrine of providence should bear on how they understand and explain occurrences in nature, what does providential naturalism look like in practice? This book answers that question by looking at a handful of figures from the past who fleshed out and implemented specific variants of providential naturalism in specific contexts. Their writings allow us to see what providential naturalisms have looked like in action. By identifying the presenting issues with which these figures dealt, the goals they had in mind when tackling those issues, and the categories and distinctions they developed and relied upon, we can get a feel for what it is like to be a providential naturalist. Equally importantly, their writings also point to the complexities and difficulties involved when God is brought to bear on the task of explanation. Even though their theological convictions about providence make room for natural causality and naturalistic forms of explanation, their writings expose some of the perennial difficulties facing Christians who want to bring their beliefs about God to the study of nature.
The authors we look at come from early modern England, and deploy that era’s Protestant theological language and conceptuality. Two features of post-Reformation England’s intellectual and religious landscape made providential naturalism a pre-eminent framework for understanding nature at the time, and therefore make it an ideal period to study. First, nature’s causal processes and mechanisms were receiving a great deal of attention because of the revolutions in natural philosophy then underway.Footnote 20 As recent surveys of the (so-called) scientific revolution attest, sixteenth- and seventeenth-century Europe was a hotbed for new ideas about nature’s causal activity: novel approaches in anatomy were being conceived; new ideas about human physiology were being developed; bold arguments suggesting that the sun is stationary and the earth is orbiting around it were being put forth; mathematics and natural philosophy were being brought together in unprecedented ways; and mechanical and other philosophies of nature were being formulated and discussed.Footnote 21 In England in particular, Francis Bacon was seeking to reform natural philosophy quite drastically, emphasising its utility for relieving the human condition. Later in the century a critical mass of eclectic scholars came together to form the Royal Society in London, an institution that nurtured the study of nature at the time, and which continues to do so to this day. Early modern England also featured natural philosophers of the stature of Robert Boyle and Isaac Newton, both of whom are pivotal figures in the history of science.Footnote 22
This widespread interest in natural causality occurred in a milieu, second, in which the influence of the Christian doctrine of providence was widespread.Footnote 23 Especially among Protestants in early modern England, belief in God’s provision was taken to be an indispensable commitment of the faith. People from all walks of life saw God in the midst of everything, and tried to understand what was taking place in their own lives, and in the world at large, in terms of God’s provision.Footnote 24 Indeed, their near obsession with providence, says historian Alexandra Walsham, led people at the time to talk, preach, and write about the topic ‘in exhaustive detail and with wearisome frequency’.Footnote 25 While intellectuals generally saw natural causality as having a vital role in God’s providential oversight of the created order, others often emphasised God’s supernatural activity in nature. For these ‘hotter sort’ of providentialists,Footnote 26 God was believed to act within the created order with considerable frequency, and unusual occurrences were thought to convey messages to humanity directly from the deity.
Providence and natural causality may later have become estranged from one another, with the former associated primarily with the category of ‘religion’ and the latter with ‘science’.Footnote 27 Among the early modern English intellectuals we look at in this book, however, providence and natural causality together in the form of providential naturalism constituted a complete picture of the world. This integrated picture was a common way of looking at nature at the time.Footnote 28 Providential naturalism’s flexibility in accommodating different views about the proportion of phenomena produced by natural causality meant that providential naturalists of a more supernatural temperament could dial down the extent of naturalism as desired, whereas those who saw nature as more regular or mechanical could move closer to the fully naturalistic end of the spectrum. Different versions of providential naturalism could also be informed by quite different underlying metaphysical commitments. While it may have been operationalised in a range of different ways depending on the convictions of those involved, early modern providential naturalism reflected long-held Christian views about the divine origins of nature and its corresponding orderliness. As a popular and flexible framework for understanding nature and explaining occurrences within it, providential naturalism informed discussions of a range of contemporary issues, and shaped debates in crucial ways.
The writings of the early modern intellectuals whom we look at address many different aspects of providential naturalism. Thanks to their thoroughness, we will see both that a consistent set of convictions lies at the heart of providential naturalisms, and that a range of complex and difficult theological issues lurks just beneath the surface. In the following chapters we focus on three challenging areas – ones that each figure, to a greater or lesser extent, grappled with in their writings – that emerge when trying to explain phenomena in the light of God’s government of the created order. The first pertains to the boundary between the natural and the miraculous. The questions here are legion: Do miracles occur? Do they still occur? Under what conditions might one expect miracles to occur? What are the criteria for judging whether any given occurrence is genuinely miraculous or not? Does God create causally efficacious entities that are (to some extent) causally autonomous, or is God causally responsible for all things in nature? The second concerns nature’s communicative aspect, an area that similarly raises a host of questions: To what extent, and by what means, does nature reveal God? Does nature communicate God’s purposes for human beings? What is the relationship between natural causality and the communicativity of nature? The third pertains to the relationship between what happens in nature, how we explain those phenomena, and how we should live. Although not all of the authors we look at treated these issues in equal depth, their writings indicate them to be pressing concerns that they simply could not avoid addressing, and suggest that they are ones which any prospective providential naturalist will eventually confront.
The case studies examined here enable discernment of both the possibilities and the challenges – or the challenges latent within the possibilities – of providential naturalism as an approach to understanding and explaining what happens in nature. Even though these intellectuals come from what may seem to be a completely different world from our own, understanding how they implemented providential naturalism, and identifying the struggles they experienced along the way, illuminates the challenges that anyone employing a similar approach in other places and times will likely encounter. For anyone today for whom providential naturalism is a live option, that is, understanding the assumptions and judgements these past providential naturalists had to make, and the challenges they faced, reveals some of the complications today’s providential naturalists may encounter. At the same time, for those who are sceptical of religiously inflected explanations of phenomena in nature, or who prefer non-religious forms of naturalism for any reason, a close look at how past intellectuals thought about phenomena in nature from within a providential vision of the world will sharpen the sceptic’s questions about, and criticisms of, comparable explanatory efforts in other historical circumstances.
Contents of the Book
The doctrine of providence traditionally has shaped how Christians view nature. In early modern English Protestant thought the doctrine enveloped natural causality and deployed it in a variety of ways, with God’s government of the created order often believed to occur through the operation of natural causes. To grasp how natural causality was perceived at the time we must therefore appreciate the broader providential context within which naturally caused phenomena were located. Chapter 2 looks at how English Protestants understood some of the main categories used to expound providence: creation, conservation, concurrence, government, ordinary and special providence, and others. These categories appear in one form or another in the texts discussed in later chapters. Understanding their meaning and purpose here makes it easier to appreciate their significance in those contexts.
Christians have long made use of naturalistic forms of explanation to explain phenomena in nature. At times, they have even wielded it against fellow Christians in the hope of replacing excessively miraculous explanations with more naturalistic ones, or of exchanging what are thought to be defective expressions of Christian piety with more acceptable ones. Chapters 3 and 4 examine specific instances of this kind of naturalistic critique amidst competing partially naturalistic explanations of the same phenomena.
Chapter 3 looks at chance-based gambling activities like dice and lots. Early modern Protestants thought gambling through such instruments was a big societal problem. This chapter analyses competing partially naturalistic accounts of how these activities were understood. It focusses on clergyman Thomas Gataker’s deployment of a more naturalistic approach, as an alternative to the more supernaturalistic approaches that some of his fellow Protestants, such as James Balmford, were using to fight back against the problem. At first glance these activities may not seem like the other kinds of phenomena in nature studied elsewhere in the book, but to early modern thinkers they involved very similar causal mechanisms to many other kinds of occurrences in nature. They therefore shed considerable light on how Christians at the time thought about and explained many kinds of phenomena in nature.
Chapter 4 turns to prodigies, unusual or unexpected phenomena thought to be personally or communally meaningful. Prodigies were widely thought to be an integral feature of a providentially governed world, and many different occurrences were taken to be communicative signs of God’s disposition toward, or impending judgement of, humanity. Some saw these strange occurrences as miracles and hence instances of divine action, but others dismissed such views as superstitious and misinformed, and conceived of ways to correct them. Following the lead of Francis Bacon, the English scholar John Spencer was convinced that the explanation of these unusual occurrences should be reformed, and made the case for placing them under the purview of natural philosophy and explaining them naturalistically. This chapter looks at the occurrences that Spencer labelled as prodigies, his strategies for understanding them, the consequences of providing naturalistic explanations of prodigies for the perceived communicative capacities of nature, and the afterlife of Spencer’s analysis among members of the Royal Society.
Chapters 5 and 6 examine how partially naturalistic explanation proceeded within the context of selected new philosophies of nature that emerged during the seventeenth century. Historians often see these new philosophies as part of an early modern shift toward a more regular, mechanical, or deterministic cosmos than was typically assumed by the broadly Aristotelian natural philosophies which they were intended to replace. As such, they generally expanded the number of phenomena in nature that were simply assumed to be explicable naturalistically compared to the number that were assumed to be in the philosophies that came before them.Footnote 29 These two chapters look at specific instances of these new philosophies, and examine how they were operationalised by intellectuals who nevertheless insisted that God providentially governs the cosmos. So while Chapters 3 and 4 look at figures who wanted to expand the remit of natural causality and naturalistic explanation in the midst of providential theologies that tended to emphasise the supernatural end of the providential naturalism spectrum, Chapters 5 and 6 discuss figures who faced quite a different challenge: meaningfully maintaining God’s providential oversight of a cosmos amidst new philosophies which potentially could conceive of that cosmos as entirely orderly and regular in its operation.
Chapter 5 looks at Epicurean atomism as it was articulated by the physician and natural philosopher Walter Charleton. Charleton was among the first in England to advocate for a Christianised version of Epicureanism, a philosophy long considered suspicious because of its purportedly atheistic implications. Charleton countered these concerns by situating Epicurean atomism within a providential picture of the world. This chapter examines the main elements of Charleton’s partially naturalistic worldview, the influence of atomism on his providential naturalism, and his understanding of the affective consequences of invoking natural causality in a providentially governed world.
Chapter 6 delves into early modern theories about a key scriptural story, that of Noah’s flood, and the theological implications of explaining the flood in a largely naturalistic manner through appeal to laws of nature. Seventeenth-century French philosopher René Descartes used laws of nature as the basis for a naturalistic account of the creation of the world, and others quickly followed suit. This chapter analyses two accounts of the world’s creation and subsequent dissolution in the flood written in England in the closing decades of the seventeenth century that drew on laws of nature: Thomas Burnet’s Sacred Theory of the Earth, and William Whiston’s New Theory of the Earth. In their respective treatises, Burnet and Whiston explore how those early events in the earth’s history might be accounted for through natural processes, making their treatises among the earliest explicit attempts in England to explain key scriptural events chiefly in terms of natural causality. This chapter focusses on how each nevertheless retained a partially naturalistic approach to their naturalistic explanatory endeavours.
Chapters 3 to 6 display what selected early modern providential naturalisms looked like in action. Each chapter concludes with some observations about the providential naturalism framework analysed in that chapter, and some questions about implementing those frameworks more generally, that arise from these scenarios. Those observations and questions are ones that emerged either directly (through an author’s explicit discussion of them), or indirectly (because an author’s treatment of an issue prompts them). The concluding chapter of the book (Chapter 7) draws these together to better understand what might be involved in being a providential naturalist today. It identifies some of the key theological ideas, assumptions, and judgements involved in providential naturalisms, and some significant challenges and complexities that providential naturalists in any time and place will likely need to navigate. In terms of the latter, it draws attention specifically to the three areas of concern – the boundary between the natural and the miraculous; the communicative qualities of nature; and the implications of naturalistic explanation for how to live one’s life – described above.