Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-669899f699-g7b4s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-04-27T18:37:46.107Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Part II - Tools of Private Law

Torts, Contracts, and Property as Vehicles of Health Policy Introduction

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 March 2025

I. Glenn Cohen
Affiliation:
Harvard Law School, Massachusetts
Susannah Baruch
Affiliation:
Harvard Law School, Massachusetts
Wendy Netter Epstein
Affiliation:
DePaul University, Chicago
Christopher Robertson
Affiliation:
Boston University
Carmel Shachar
Affiliation:
Harvard Law School, Massachusetts
Type
Chapter
Information
Health Law as Private Law
Pathology or Pathway
, pp. 57 - 118
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2025
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NC
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

This part takes up the quintessential tools of private law – torts, contracts, and property – and considers their potential for fixing what ails our health care system. The list of problems in need of solutions is long. But at the top of that list are cost – we spend twice as much per person on health as peer nations – quality – we perform worse than peer nations in important quality metrics – and access – too many Americans are uninsured, underinsured, or otherwise lack equitable access to care.

The authors in the chapters that follow take a nuanced approach to a wide range of issues impacting health policy. They don’t all agree on whether private law is the right tool to deploy, or whether we should instead be turning to public law, such as statutory or regulatory fixes. What emerges is a view that private law can be a useful tool, particularly when public law fixes are inadequate or unavailable, but that it cannot solve all problems.

The first two chapters consider the promise of tort law. Mark A. Hall, in Chapter 7 “Adaptation of Tort Law to Modern Health Care Delivery in the Restatement of Medical Malpractice,” takes up the classic example of medical liability law. As a reporter for the American Law Institute’s first project to restate medical liability law, he explores whether tort law is meeting the needs of a rapidly evolving health care system that bears little resemblance to its much simpler origins. Hall discusses three examples from the new Restatement: the formation of a treatment relationship, the scope of individual liability when professionals work in treatment teams, and the extent to which institutions may be liable for medical error. In a nuanced discussion, he concludes that tort law’s dual features of inertia and adaptability make it capable of evolving as practice evolves but also make it not well suited to leading reform.

Alberto De Diego-Habel, Jill Horwitz, and Daniel Rodriguez also consider the promise of tort law – in their case, to both compensate for and deter pandemic harms. The harm that flowed from COVID-19 was immense, not just in the loss of over 1 million American lives but also in the health and economic consequences for many more. In their chapter (Chapter 8), “Pandemic Harms and Private Law’s Limits: A Proposal for Tort Replacement,” they argue that civil tort claims proved an inadequate legal tool and will continue to be ill-suited to address the harms of future pandemics. Difficulty proving causation largely stymied the usefulness of tort to COVID-19 victims. But it is also not clear that a better result would have been opening up the floodgates of liability to businesses already operating in a tenuous time. Instead, they argue that a publicly administered tort-replacement scheme – a form of compensation through social insurance – would be a better alternative in providing quicker, more efficient, more equitable compensation to those harmed, while also providing finality and certainty to businesses.

Two chapters then take on the promise and peril of using contract law as a vehicle of health policy.

In their chapter (Chapter 6), “States as Contractor: Attempts to Drive Health Care Cost Containment through State Purchasing Power,” Christine H. Monahan, Maanasa Kona, and Madeline O’Brien describe how states, functioning as “de facto private actors,” are using their contract powers to further public policy goals like cost containment. Some states use their gatekeeping power over their state-based ACA exchange to negotiate lower prices and better product offerings. States can extract concessions from insurers who seek access to state enrollees. Other states have contracted with private insurers to offer market-based public options, which advance cost containment goals without requiring a state to operate its own health insurance plan. State employee health plans also leverage their contracting power to contain costs, primarily by using their market power to negotiate lower reimbursement rates. In a world where regulatory price control might be the first-best option for cost containment but is politically infeasible, Monahan, Kona, and O’Brien see promise in state contractual approaches to control cost.

Craig Konnoth’s chapter (Chapter 5), “Data Transparency, ERISA Preemption, and Freedom of Contract,” similarly describes a complicated interplay between private actors, state law, and freedom of contract. Specifically, Konnoth takes on the recent proliferation of state laws aiming to improve transparency in health care, including regulation promoting All Payers’ Claims Databases, requiring disclosure of pharmaceutical pricing methodology, and obligating plans and providers to disclose network status to guard against surprise medical bills. As a category, transparency laws serve a public regulatory function, but also support private market functioning, providing information to support consumers in making more informed choices. Courts have been finding state transparency laws to be preempted by ERISA. But Konnoth argues that courts may be more likely to reject ERISA preemption challenges if they consider the role transparency laws play in supporting contracting between private parties. Konnoth turns the original question on its head, addressing the extent to which public law or regulation should be used to improve the functioning of private markets.

Finally, in Chapter 9 “The Human Body Commons: A Private Law Contribution for the Advancement of the Right to Health,” Enrique Santamaría Echeverría takes on the important problem of the privatization of research, which can hinder innovation to promote collective health. Echeverria acknowledges the difficulty of the problem. On the one hand, keeping scientific knowledge in the public domain has tremendous value for researchers who seek to build on each other’s work. On the other hand, innovation is spurred along by a promise of profits, which incentivizes innovators to protect their work from the public domain. Recognizing both the importance of the profit motive and the benefits of open access to research, Echeverria explores how private law, including contracts and property rights, can promote both interests.

These chapters together suggest important, continuing roles for tort, contract, and property law to promote the health and welfare of society. But they also highlight the insufficiency of these tools standing alone. Policymakers and lawmakers will have to continue to wrestle with how private law can be used to bolster systemic goals, but also with which policy goals and reform efforts require statutory and regulatory intervention.

5 Data Transparency, ERISA Preemption, and Freedom of Contract

Craig Konnoth
Footnote *
5.1 Introduction

In recent years, an increasingly libertarian judiciary has struck down a range of health care transparency regulation under the Employee Retirement and Income Security Act (ERISA). ERISA preempts state laws that “relate to” employee benefit plans.Footnote 1 This test is an indeterminate one,Footnote 2 and thus, lower courts bolster their analysis with policy considerations in striking down these laws.

Several scholars, including myself, have argued that invalidating these transparency laws is undesirable for various reasons.Footnote 3 I do not seek to reprise that debate here. Rather, this chapter focuses on rebutting a specific policy consideration that courts advance when invalidating transparency laws – namely, that such laws undermine freedom of contract by forcing plaintiffs to disclose information in violation of contracts to which they are parties. This chapter identifies a doctrinal thread in ERISA cases that rebuts such freedom of contract claims using freedom of choice arguments: indeed, as various cases hold, it is freedom of choice that truly vindicates freedom of contract values. Based on those cases, I argue that transparency laws advance both freedom of choice and contract by giving parties necessary information.

Advancing this argument is important. State defendants generally highlight the public regulatory interests that transparency laws serve. But many market-oriented judges are less attuned to the goals of public regulation. Advancing arguments that vindicate market- and contract-based values might prove more successful.

The chapter begins by describing how courts have invalidated significant amounts of state transparency regulation, including regulation pertaining to All Payers’ Claims Databases (APCDs),Footnote 4 pharmacy data,Footnote 5 and surprise billing prohibitions.Footnote 6 Sections 5.3 and 5.4 then explain how, to justify ERISA preemption of state law, courts invoke policy arguments sounding in freedom of contract.

While such arguments have a powerful resonance, Section 5.5 traces a line of ERISA cases, namely those involving any willing provider (AWP) laws, in which state defendants neutralized freedom of contract claims by advancing freedom of choice arguments. It also looks to historical contract law cases, which juxtaposed freedom of choice and freedom of contract to hold that ultimately, freedom of choice helped vindicate true freedom of contract values.

Section 5.6 lays out the argument that transparency laws furthers freedom of choice, and, resultantly, of contract. States have generally offered arguments sounding in public regulatory interests, such as cost- and quality-control to defend these laws. I argue that presenting transparency rationales as ways to allow informed consumers to make choices to promote well-functioning markets may produce better outcomes before market-oriented judges. By forcing information availability, data transparency laws promote contracting in the private market as did AWP laws.

5.2 Transparency Legislation

“[H]ealth care price transparency initiatives are all the rage.”Footnote 7 While the Affordable Care Act and subsequent federal legislation have taken significant steps to promote transparency, states have been at the forefront of the effort. Three initiatives have received significant commentary.

The first are laws that promote APCDs – databases containing information that providers send to insurance companies for reimbursement.Footnote 8 Many state laws require health insurance companies to submit this data to a state agency.Footnote 9 APCDs serve a dual purpose: first, giving states information to address public health crises like COVID-19 and opioid misuse, and, second, cross-checking health data accuracy, calculating reimbursement rates, and the like. The databases also promote price transparency as they supply information to consumers and health care providers.

Next, starting in 2016, numerous states have passed bills requiring pharmacy benefits managers (PBMs) to report pricing methodology to state insurance commissioners and, often, to the pharmacies with which they contract. Information includes “increases in list prices, … aggregated dollar amount of rebates, [and] fees or price concessions provided by manufacturers.”Footnote 10

A third category in which states have shown a pattern of promoting health transparency is in the context of surprise billing by out-of-network providers. Several states have enacted regulations requiring plans and providers to disclose information about network participation so that patients are not surprised by the higher costs incurred from going to out-of-network providers.Footnote 11 As of 2022, federal legislation also provides out-of-network coverage protection,Footnote 12 but some state laws go further.Footnote 13

5.3 ERISA Preemption Cases

ERISA preempts state laws that “relate to” employee benefit plans.Footnote 14 The inquiry has two prongs. First, a state law that makes “reference” to a plan is preempted. Next, laws that have a “connection to” ERISA plans are also invalid.Footnote 15 This chapter will not analyze this test in detail. Suffice it to say that a series of cases have invalidated state transparency laws under this test.

In Gobeille v. Liberty Mutual, the Supreme Court invalidated data collection mandates for self-insured employers in APCDs under the “connection to” prong of the preemption test. According to the Court, the APCD reporting law would “govern, or interfere with the uniformity of, plan administration and so ha[s] an impermissible connection with ERISA plans.”Footnote 16 As a result of the ruling, 60 percent of all employers can ignore information mandates in their states.Footnote 17

A year after Gobeille, in Pharmaceutical Care Management Association v. Gerhart, the Eighth Circuit targeted the second category of transparency regulation—PBM reporting, under both prongs of the preemption test. Gerhart held first that, because the state PBM statute explicitly exempted certain ERISA plans from compliance, the statute therefore made explicit "reference” to the plans.Footnote 18 Then, for good measure, the court also relied on Gobeille to hold that the law failed under the “connection to” prong. PBMs act as third-party administrators of pharmacy benefits for ERISA plans, reasoned the court. Referencing Gobeille’s language that I quote above, the court held that a law that “compels PBMs as third-party administrators to report to the commissioner and to network pharmacies their [reimbursement] methodology” therefore “intrudes upon a matter central to plan administration and interferes with nationally uniform plan administration.”Footnote 19

Notwithstanding subsequent Supreme Court case law on PBM legislation, Gerhart remains – in part – good law. In 2020, the Supreme Court upheld a state law requiring PBMs to reimburse pharmacies at higher rates. The Court noted that the PBM regulation does not “refer” to an ERISA plan as it “does not act immediately and exclusively upon ERISA plans because it applies to PBMs whether or not they manage an ERISA plan.”Footnote 20 Gerhart’s “reference to” analysis thus no longer survives. But Gerhart’s analysis under the “connection with” prong remains intact.Footnote 21

5.4 The Freedom of Contract Backdrop

The cases above purport to rely on formalistic analysis, and scholars treat Gobeille in particular as a straightforward example of ERISA preemption.Footnote 22 But ERISA doctrinal analysis is indeterminate.Footnote 23 As a practical matter, courts invoke policy considerations such as uniformity of administration or burdens on administrators, and scholars have commented on these policy claims. But one policy justification that has received no attention is that concerning freedom of contract.

As I argue elsewhere, there was more to Gobeille than met the eye. The employer’s ERISA plan argued in its briefing that preemption of state law was required because the state regulation displaced contracts between beneficiaries and the insurance company, which, it claimed, required keeping data confidential.Footnote 24 Significant text was devoted to this argument by the United States Solicitor General’s Office before the ERISA plan even filed its brief.Footnote 25 This debate over the importance of respecting contracts was strange: While the Supreme Court in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries was sympathetic to plaintiffs who challenged state laws that, they claimed, undermined freedom of contract under the Contract Clause, since the New Deal, this approach to the Contract Clause has been repudiated. State law has generally been understood to govern contract terms.Footnote 26

Despite the demise of freedom of contract arguments in constitutional doctrine, they retained a strange afterlife in ERISA cases. The earliest ERISA preemption cases in the 1970s concerned pension benefits,Footnote 27 with plaintiffs complaining that ERISA undermined freedom of contract in pension arrangements. Courts replied that that was exactly what ERISA was meant to do. As an Alabama district court wrote in 1979, with ERISA, “freedom of contract was largely eliminated from the world of pension agreements.”Footnote 28 That line of thinking filtered its way into courts of appeals.Footnote 29

While freedom of contract arguments failed in the 1970s pension cases, in the 1980s, employers brought a new set of preemption cases, claiming that state laws regarding health plans were preempted. By this time academic, and then, judicial, attitudes to freedom of contract had changed, and courts took a different tack.Footnote 30 A decade after one Alabama district court opinion repudiated freedom of contract principles in pension plans, another Alabama district court held that those principles remained alive and well in welfare benefit plans: “Congress included welfare benefit plans within the scheme of ERISA, but did not provide an extensive array of mandatory provisions as it did for pension plans. The implication here is that parties retain a greater degree of freedom to contract between themselves as to what benefits will be provided under welfare plans.”Footnote 31 This language became boilerplate in judicial opinions that emphasized the importance of freedom of contract in welfare benefit plans.Footnote 32

While there were some asides in opinions that recognized the limitations of freedom of contract doctrine,Footnote 33 in a small but steady diet of cases since the 1980s through today, courts have infused the policy analysis that characteristically underlies ERISA preemption cases with freedom of contract claims. One district court linked the “‘vital public interest’ in health care cost containment … with the traditional freedom to contract as one pleases.”Footnote 34 Another emphasized that “the public has an interest in protecting the freedom to contract by enforcing contractual rights and obligations.”Footnote 35 And in 2017, a court held that “[r]equiring … compl[iance] with … plan[] procedures not only respects freedom of contract, but will also serve important purposes,” relating to the ERISA dispute resolution process.Footnote 36 Every court to invoke freedom of contract has found that ERISA preempts the state statute. Even though freedom of contract is never the centerpiece of the holdings, its appearance is notable.

ERISA preemption cases involving transparency statutes also endorse contract principles (albeit not as explicitly as the ERISA preemption cases I describe above). The Gobeille Court began its application of ERISA doctrine by observing that “ERISA does not guarantee substantive benefits. The statute, instead, seeks to make the benefits promised by an employer more secure by mandating certain oversight systems and other standard procedures.”Footnote 37 Similarly, the offense in Gerhart is described as “dictating the manner by which PBMs contract with pharmacies regarding … pricing.”Footnote 38

5.5 Rebutting Freedom of Contract – The AWP Cases

How might one address the freedom of contract anxiety that courts evince in striking down transparency statutes? One answer might lie in a line of cases that successfully defeated these arguments – those concerning AWP statutes.

These statutes require insurers or PBMs to contract with any provider willing to abide by their terms to prevent insurers from limiting costs by artificially throttling the ability of individuals to access care.Footnote 39 By 1986, eight states had passed these AWP statutes,Footnote 40 leading to some of the earliest ERISA preemption litigation. But outcomes conflicted. Two circuits held that ERISA preempted these laws; two circuits held the opposite.Footnote 41

Those supporting the laws argued that even if these laws “relate[d] to” a plan, and therefore met ERISA’s preemption test, they survived under a preemption exception which allowed states to “regulate[] insurance.”Footnote 42 The Supreme Court, through Justice Scalia, sided with this view in Kentucky Association of Health Plans v. Miller.Footnote 43

The doctrine surrounding the insurance savings clause, as the Court admits in Miller itself,Footnote 44 is far from clear.Footnote 45 Indeed, commentators have suggested that Miller was “self-contradictory” and probably unworkable.Footnote 46 Just as courts rely on policy arguments to determine whether state laws “relate to” an ERISA plan in the first place because of the term’s indeterminacy, those parsing the insurance savings clause also invoke policy claims – including freedom of contract arguments.

The previous section notes that in ERISA health preemption cases, courts that mention freedom of contract arguments do so to hold that the state laws are invalid. The AWP cases are no exception. In CIGNA Healthplan of Louisiana v. Ieyoub, the first lawsuit that resulted in appellate invalidation of an AWP law,Footnote 47 the plaintiffs sought freedom of contract as an independent ground of relief. They argued both that “the Any Willing Provider Statute is preempted by ERISA” and, “[a]s an alternative claim, … that the statute violates the Due Process Clause … because it interferes with the plaintiffs’ freedom to contract with health care providers of their choice.”Footnote 48 In a ruling affirmed on appeal, the court held that ERISA preempted the AWP law. Similarly, in a lower court ruling in the Eighth Circuit (the other jurisdiction to invalidate AWP laws) the court explained that the effect of AWP laws “on ERISA plans is to eliminate their freedom to contract with HMOs.”Footnote 49 In the other AWP cases as well, petitioners advanced arguments that sounded in freedom of contract – ultimately, and unsuccessfully – at the Supreme Court.Footnote 50

But two circuits, and later, the Supreme Court, upheld these laws and rejected ERISA preemption. In these cases, freedom of contract was never mentioned. Rather, courts emphasized a different concept – freedom of choice. As proponents of AWP statutes emphasized, the laws allowed consumers to choose providers they wanted. For instance, in Stuart Circle v. Aetna, the court explained that the state legislature had given “priority to an insured’s freedom to choose doctors and hospitals over the possibility of reduced insurance premiums …. The wisdom of this decision is a concern of the legislature, not the judiciary.”Footnote 51

Five years later, faced with the challenge that would mature into Miller, the district court quoted extensively from Stuart Circle, and noted that “freedom to choose a treating physician is inextricable from the nature of the coverage provided.”Footnote 52 On appeal, the Sixth Circuit plugged the same refrain with even greater vigor. It noted that the law would “increase benefits to the insureds by giving them greater freedom to choose health care providers,”Footnote 53 and noted that policyholders were concerned with “restriction on their freedom of choice in seeking medical treatment.”Footnote 54 Indeed, the freedom of choice argument attracted the dissent’s ire. After questioning whether the AWP law actually promoted “freedom of choice,” the dissent curtly cautioned, “any concerns over freedom of choice are beside the point.”Footnote 55 The Supreme Court affirmed the majority, though without mentioning freedom of choice.

The contrast is clear. Cases coming down in favor of ERISA preemption generally, and with respect to AWP laws in particular, raise freedom of contract as one of ERISA’s aims. In the AWP context, however, courts that decided against ERISA preemption invoked freedom of choice arguments instead.

Critics might suggest that I am reading too much into these cases. After all, prominent literature that defends freedom of contract uses the terms “contract” and “choice” interchangeably,Footnote 56 as do widely cited judicial decisions,Footnote 57 and one appellate ERISA preemption case.Footnote 58 Yet, however the terms are used elsewhere, in the ERISA opinions I describe above, and in related party submissions, freedom of choice constitutes a term of art, referring to a certain subset of laws that allows patients to see providers that they prefer. And the courts in these cases, at least, do not use the term interchangeably but almost in contraposition to each other.

Indeed, we see even more explicit juxtaposition of freedom of contract and choice in other lines of cases. During the 1970s, when courts were least sympathetic to freedom of contract claims,Footnote 59 the need to ensure true freedom of choice was widely relied on as a reason to ignore formalistic adherence to contract. In an influential and widely quoted passage,Footnote 60 for example, the New Jersey Supreme Court in Kugler v. Romain defended unconscionability doctrine, by noting, “[t]he intent of the clause is not to erase the doctrine of freedom of contract, but to make realistic the assumption of the law that the agreement has resulted from real bargaining between parties who had freedom of choice and understanding and ability to negotiate in a meaningful fashion.”Footnote 61 Thus, held Kugler, “freedom to contract survives,” but is dependent on whether there is actual freedom of choice.Footnote 62

At the same time, these courts reasoned, it is a mistake to paint freedom of choice as a completely separate concept from ‘true’ freedom of contract. Indeed, many courts that relied on freedom of choice to counter freedom of contract arguments ultimately concluded that freedom of choice as they saw it enabled true freedom of contract. As the Puerto Rico Supreme Court explained in another highly cited opinion that drew limits around noncompete agreements: excessively stringent contracts “not only … violate contractual good faith but also public policy, by excessively and unjustifiably restricting the employee’s freedom of contract and the general public’s freedom of choice.”Footnote 63 As another court explained in the early years of freedom of contract’s decline, “[l]iberty of contract does not mean the right to make any kind of contract with any body but merely the right to make contracts with competent persons on a plane of relative parity or freedom of choice.”Footnote 64 Thus, “freedom of choice” considerations may undermine freedom of contract as a formal matter but ultimately advance its true goals. Such an approach to freedom of contract – which relies on whether parties have freedom of choice – has implications for the ERISA transparency cases.

5.6 Transparency Laws Further Freedom of Choice

It is hard to assess the extent to which freedom of contract arguments play a role in ERISA preemption. Yet, it would appear that increasingly market-oriented courts see freedom of contract as an important value, and view ERISA preemption as a means to vindicate it. These courts might be unsympathetic to counterarguments that draw on public regulatory goals, such as price-setting. But advancing freedom of choice arguments – which, ultimately, can be reframed as helping achieve true freedom of contract, might prove more successful.

Transparency laws in general serve dual purposes as Section 5.2 explains. For example, APCD laws serve public regulatory goals such as price setting, but also private purposes, such as providing data transparency to allow consumers and other stakeholders to negotiate with insurers. This is true of other transparency initiatives including those involving PBMs. State litigants, however, have tended to emphasize the regulatory importance of these laws.

Consider the Gerhart litigation. The state’s brief did not raise concerns about inequitable bargaining power even once. It rather emphasized the public, regulatory goals of the PBM statute. The AWP law “regulates a PBM’s reimbursement of pharmacies. It regulates the pharmacy side of PBMs’ business.”Footnote 65 Rather than explaining how the law helps pharmacies negotiate with PBMs, it emphasized how the law regulates the negotiation.

By contrast, amici heavily emphasized how the transparency laws promoted private bargaining between parties. They point to the bargaining inequity between parties: “independent pharmacies cannot simply refuse to do business with PBMs, much less insist upon fair contractual terms … as PBMs manage drug benefits for 95 percent of all Americans with prescription-drug benefits …. Thus, PBMs are able to impose take-it-or-leave-it contracts on pharmacies.” Notably, “even large pharmacies, like those managed by CVS, Walgreens, and Kmart, have struggled to secure fair treatment from PBMs.”Footnote 66 The legislation addresses these concerns because – in part – it “requires PBMs to disclose how they calculate their reimbursement amounts in any contracts with Iowa pharmacies and gives contracting pharmacies a chance to contest the reimbursement amount.”Footnote 67 In this way, their reasoning evoked the contract analysis of the courts in the AWP cases described above, who sought to promote freedom of choice.

The Gobeille briefing presented the same problem. Some – including government entities – did mention the importance of the data for private bargaining, though none of them foregrounded it as a purpose of the legislation. Thus, only after explaining how states used APCD data to address costs in their regulatory capacity did the brief of the AARP (formerly the American Association of Retired Persons) and others explain: “patients usually do not know the price of health care … [and] need information to make informed choices about … health care services, before they purchase these services – just as they would to make any other major purchase. They … need to know … whether they are getting the best value for their dollar.”Footnote 68 The American Hospital Association with the American Association of Medical Colleges first emphasized the public health regulation that APCDs achieve at length, before, in a brief paragraph, noting that the “[p]atients – especially those who personally bear a significant share of their health care costs – need reliable sources of information for determining how to spend their health care dollars,” and noting that Colorado had a website to promote this goal.Footnote 69 Other prominent briefs did the same, emphasizing a range of other significant public goals.Footnote 70 Few of these briefs mentioned, much less explained, the powerlessness that patient–consumers experience. None of them used the language of freedom of choice, which figured so prominently in the AWP cases, to defend the laws.Footnote 71

And most of the briefs – including individual briefs filed by other states and by the American Medical AssociationFootnote 72 – did not even mention how data transparency furthered consumer choice. Most notably, the brief of the Petitioner, the state of Vermont, lists the uses of the data as follows: “improve the delivery of medical care to its citizens and guide health care regulation and policy.”Footnote 73 Its Reply brief even mentions the federal uses to which the data is put.Footnote 74 Consumer and market participant needs were not mentioned.

Yet, there is a strong argument that transparency laws support freedom of choice. Colorado, New Hampshire, and Maine have each “used its APCD data to create a public website that enables its residents to compare the cost of health care services across providers within the State,” while others intend to do so. Patients can “compare costs by selecting a particular kind of health care service [say, a hip replacement], a geographical area [say, within 25 miles from Denver], and the kind of insurance to be billed …. The website would then display the median price.” The Maine website gives consumers and providers transparent information on provider performance, cost, and reimbursement.Footnote 75

Arguing that data transparency supports freedom of choice for those who would otherwise lack it may prove to be important in advancing data transparency claims in other contexts. To be sure, the Supreme Court is unlikely to revisit APCDs. But other important data transparency efforts remain ongoing, as Section 5.2 describes. Further, the Department of Labor has drafted policies that would require self-funded plans to report APCD data federally – but only on a voluntary basis, likely fearing opposition to the policies.Footnote 76 Freedom of choice arguments might prove important in those policy contexts as well – while they are used in judicial decisions, they are policy arguments to begin with.

5.7 Conclusion

Freedom of choice is not the only, or arguably, even the most important, argument for data transparency. The public values – including those emphasized and foregrounded in the Gobeille briefing – are probably more vital than providing data to consumers to enable bargaining. Even with data, consumers will lack market power.Footnote 77 Data can also prove hard to parse and analyze for consumers, especially those experiencing serious medical conditions.Footnote 78 Yet, freedom of choice arguments allow promoters of transparency laws to meet those who promote freedom of contract on their own turf and can prove to be of strategic value in advancing the cause of data transparency before market-oriented courts. Rather than emphasizing public regulatory goals, then, state defendants and policymakers should create a record that emphasizes how these databases support contracting between private parties in order to withstand ERISA preemption challenges.

6 States as Contractor Attempts to Drive Health Care Cost Containment through State Purchasing Power

Christine H. Monahan , Maanasa Kona , and Madeline O’Brien Footnote *
6.1 Introduction

US health care costs are spiraling upwards, largely because of the high and rising prices set by hospitals and other health care providers. Commercial insurers and large employers mostly pass along these high prices to consumers in the form of increased premiums and cost-sharing, leaving many Americans financially unstable. Yet political and practical barriers block reforms that seek to limit provider prices via regulation. To circumvent these barriers, several states are leveraging their role as contracting entities and players in the private health care market to further public policy goals, such as controlling health care costs.

These government engagements in the private market fall somewhere along the porous border between private and public law. In the types of contracting relationships we discuss here, we posit that the state functions as a de facto private actor. While some might argue that the state can never function as a private actor, given its outsized power and the complex body of government contracting laws set up to protect its rights, we find that the similarities between the state as a private actor and large, fully privately owned, corporations are greater than the differences between them. Large corporations similarly bring their significant, sometimes monopolistic, power to bear in negotiating their contracts, and leverage centuries-old commercial laws to enforce those contracts. Both types of entities use their market position and legally provided protections to work toward their ultimate goals, which in the case of privately owned entities is profit, and in the case of state actors is the advancement of public policy goals such as saving taxpayer dollars or making health care affordable.

In this chapter, we explore three examples of states turning to different types of typically private roles to try to lower commercial health care costs. First, we discuss how states can leverage their role as marketplace operators, like Amazon or Apple (vis a vis the “App” Store), to serve as a conduit between sellers and purchasers of insurance. This role allows states to engage in selective contracting practices with insurer-sellers to drive down premiums and drive up the value of the products offered on the marketplace. This is a tactic many envisioned as a best practice for marketplaces created under the Affordable Care Act (ACA). Second, we will turn to recent efforts by states like Washington to newly enter the private health insurance market by enacting public health insurance options in partnership with private health insurers. These efforts are also intended to bring to the market more high-value, low-cost insurance products to consumers. Third, we will examine how some states leverage their long-standing role as purchasers of health insurance to achieve cost containment. States, like most large, private employers, provide health insurance to their workers, retirees, and their dependents through employee health plans, and in any given state, the state employee health plan (SEHP) is one of the largest, if not the largest, purchasers of health benefit services from commercial insurers, who act as third-party administrators.

States have seen varying degrees of success and encountered different barriers, when engaging with the health insurance market in these three different roles. Other analyses of states engaging in the private market often focus on the merits of privatizing public programs and functions to reduce the size and scope of government and how these efforts risk the watering down of legal rights, remedies, and other protections for beneficiaries.Footnote 1 By contrast, our examples allow “agencies [to] extend their influence to matters and actors that they could not otherwise lawfully reach” and shape the market to achieve public interest goals.Footnote 2 Despite their promise, however, we find that market-driven reforms can only do so much when the marketplace is already as broken as the US health care system is. Nonetheless, they can still serve as intermediate steps on the way to a better-functioning health care market pending broader reforms to our health care delivery and payment systems.

6.2 Roadblocks to Containing Health Care Costs

The United States spends about twice as much as other high-income countries on health care, while performing relatively poorly on population health outcomes.Footnote 3 These high costs are not driven by US patients using more services or the United States providing particularly high-quality care. Instead, they largely stem from the prices commercial insurers pay for hospital and physician services.Footnote 4

Commercial insurers and group health plans in the United States pay for the health care of about 177 million people, and they pay significantly more than public insurers like Medicare and Medicaid for the same services.Footnote 5 In response to rising health care prices, these payers have shifted more of the cost burden to plan enrollees through higher premiums and out-of-pocket costs.Footnote 6 Given their ability to shift costs and market pressures to maintain good relationships with health care providers, commercial insurers have little incentive to negotiate lower prices with providers, and may in fact have an incentive to inflate spending because their profits are tied to a percentage of premiums collected (in the fully insured markets, due to federal medical loss ratio requirements) or claims paid (in self-insured markets, where insurers are administering plans funded by employers and employees).Footnote 7

Insurers’ insufficient incentive to negotiate lower prices, combined with rapid provider market consolidation, has given health care providers outsized leverage when contracting with insurers, and made it unlikely for the existing commercial insurance market to achieve meaningful cost containment absent government intervention. In response, experts and policymakers have debated a range of regulatory strategies to try and contain costs in the commercial sector and have largely reached the same conclusion: “the only solution that may be effective in a concentrated provider market is regulation of health care prices.”Footnote 8 Yet few states currently regulate commercial health care prices and, with the exception of Maryland, efforts that have been made have generally been indirect (e.g., setting cost growth benchmarks) or narrowly focused (e.g., preventing “surprise” billing by out-of-network providers).Footnote 9 In the 1970s and 1980s, many more states directly regulated prices, but this fell out of favor for many interconnected reasons, including the general philosophical and political shift toward market-based mechanisms in the 1990s and the advent of managed care organizations promising to control costs via internal mechanisms.Footnote 10

Renewed efforts to meaningfully regulate health care costs have failed largely due to political barriers.Footnote 11 The hospital industry holds significant political power and strongly opposes price regulation.Footnote 12 Because the insurance industry also profits from higher health spending, their interests are aligned.Footnote 13 Many policymakers also prefer a lighter regulatory touch, pushing back against government actions that can be seen as unduly affecting market dynamics.Footnote 14 When implemented, even narrow regulatory reforms face legal challenges and obstruction from industry.Footnote 15

Given these obstacles, policymakers are turning to reforms that make use of government purchasing power and contracting tools, as more politically attractive and easier to implement. We explore three examples of states leveraging their contracting authority and purchasing power, rather than their regulatory authority, to lower health care costs in the private health insurance market. Although the reach of these reforms is narrower than traditional regulatory reforms, we explore the extent to which states can use them to effect incremental change while waiting for political winds to return in favor of price regulation.

6.3 Wielding a Lighter Touch: Can States Contract to Lower Health Care Prices?
6.3.1 Health Insurance Marketplaces

A health insurance exchange or marketplace is a state-operated one-stop shop where consumers or businesses can compare and enroll in health insurance products. The marketplace serves as the key connection point between insurance plans and consumer purchasers, similar to how Apple’s iTunes store connects artists looking to sell their music with fans looking to purchase it. And, just as Apple separately contracts with music artists before they can sell music on iTunes, the state enters into contracts with private health insurers seeking to sell their plans through the state-run exchanges. Experts envisioned that states would engage in a practice known as “active purchasing,” and negotiate with several insurers to extract better insurance products and lower rates for the products that eventually end up on the marketplace.Footnote 16 States and employers can achieve this by employing selective contracting practices, such as competitive bidding and negotiation processes, to advance goals like cost containment. By requiring private insurers to compete against each other to earn the ability to participate in the marketplace, these practices harness traditional forces of market competition to nudge private actors to provide a more robust product. If the marketplace is not attractive to insurers, however, they can opt out and offer their plans to consumers off-marketplace.

The first successful active-purchasing marketplace was established by the Massachusetts Connector Authority in 2006. The Authority created a system of two separate marketplaces: Commonwealth Care for low-income individuals who qualify for state-funded subsidies, and Commonwealth Choice for non-state-subsidized individuals and small businesses. By making Commonwealth Care the sole source of state subsidies, Massachusetts could create a “captive” market, with all subsidy-eligible consumers incentivized to participate in Commonwealth Care rather than shopping elsewhere and paying full price.Footnote 17 This captive market encouraged insurer participation. As a result, the state had enough insurers wanting to participate that it was able to selectively contract with insurers. The Connector authority also structured marketplace rules to encourage lower bids from insurers: for example, automatically enrolling participants who signed up but failed to choose a plan in the lowest-cost option, and administering risk-sharing to protect plans against the risks of enrolling disproportionally expensive enrollees.Footnote 18 These decisions resulted in annual premium increases with half the growth rate of private insurance.Footnote 19

Massachusetts served as a model for federal lawmakers designing the ACA, but ten years into implementation of the ACA marketplaces, California is the only other state to take similarly aggressive measures. Marketplace officials report that they “extract[] concessions on price and product design as a condition for having access to the largest pool of new enrollees in the state” and have “excluded plans that have not demonstrated the administrative capability, prices, networks, or product designs that improve consumer value.”Footnote 20 Additionally, the marketplace “jawbones down premiums to the extent it can, leveraging its private information on risk mix, competitor rates, and the price elasticity of demand.”Footnote 21 Studies suggest that these reforms have had a positive effect on the individual market. California’s premiums have grown more slowly than national averages, marketplace enrollment is one of the highest in the country, and statewide average risk scores have been in the bottom 10 percent of states each year for both on-and-off marketplace plans.Footnote 22

Some other state marketplaces and the federal marketplace have taken more cautious approaches, primarily focused on improving the quality and adequacy of coverage by requiring insurers to agree to certain minimum standards as a condition of marketplace participation. But these marketplaces have been reluctant to push for lower premiums using the best tool available to them – selective contracting with those insurers offering the most competitive rates or engaging in California-style “jawbone” negotiations.

There are several explanations for this hesitancy. In some states, proponents of limited government object to states employing these contracting tactics because they perceive it as the state controlling insurer access to the marketplace – Colorado explicitly prohibits their marketplace from “solicit[ing] bids or engag[ing] in the active purchasing of insurance.”Footnote 23 Some experts also have argued that states cannot justify the expenditure of resources required to engage in active purchasing, since they do not foot the cost of premiums.Footnote 24 Market dynamics, including increasing insurer consolidation, likely play the biggest role, however.

Few insurers participated in the individual and small group markets served by ACA marketplaces, when the law was passed. To encourage greater insurer participation while simultaneously increasing the minimum standards insurers must meet to serve these markets, the ACA provided federal financial assistance only to consumers who purchase coverage through the marketplaces and established risk adjustment and reinsurance programs to minimize adverse selection. Despite these efforts, individual and small group markets continue to be largely dominated by a small number of insurers. This leaves most marketplaces with little leverage to threaten to exclude one or more insurers in a bidding or negotiation process. Even in states with relatively unconsolidated insurer markets, marketplaces can be hesitant to restrict consumer choice – “the bedrock of the American economy and, increasingly, of the American health economy”Footnote 25 – in the name of cost containment. A marketplace with just one or two insurers may struggle to compete with less-regulated and cheaper plans offered outside the marketplace to attract consumers, especially those who do not qualify for significant marketplace subsidies.

In order for states to be able to follow Massachusetts’ and California’s leads to fully exert the powers of private law and extract lower premiums, they must (1) remove any barriers preventing marketplaces from using the full arsenal of contractual tools available to them and (2) push against the forces of consolidation that are throttling the performance of the health insurance market. One such mechanism is our next example of states increasing competition in the private market in nontraditional ways: by establishing a new state public health insurance option to compete against private insurers’ products.

6.3.2 Market-Based Public Options

Traditionally, a public option is a publicly insured health plan that competes against private insurers. With these plans, the state is engaging in the private market itself and subject to the same rules as a private insurer. However, because the government controls provider reimbursement rates and lacks a profit motive, public option plans can be a tool to lower health care costs and expand coverage, while expanding consumer choice.

No such plan exists today, albeit not for lack of trying; these proposals have faced steep practical barriers. Establishing and financing a new health insurance plan is no small endeavor, particularly for budget-strapped state governments. Like other cost containment reforms, public option proposals garner significant opposition from industry groups seeking to preserve the status quo, and activists and legislators hoping to minimize government involvement in health care. Nonetheless, two states – Washington and Nevada – have enacted laws authorizing the state to contract with private insurers to offer new “Market-Based Public Options” (MBPOs), advancing state cost containment and other policy goals without the government directly taking on the financial and administrative burden of operating a health insurance plan.Footnote 26

To effectuate these MBPOs, states must get the insurers and providers that vehemently opposed enactment of these programs to participate. And because these plans are starting with no covered lives, states cannot woo insurers or providers with the promise of a large volume of enrollees. Although states could use their regulatory power to simply mandate participation, both Washington and Nevada have instead sought to leverage their purchasing power to encourage insurers and providers to participate, more akin to how a private company may engage with suppliers. Of the two, Washington warrants the closest consideration; its program has been in operation for three years while Nevada’s remains in the planning stages.

Washington’s initial approach to both insurer and provider participation was purely voluntary: The state imposed no explicit incentives or disincentives for insurers to offer MBPOs or providers to join MBPO networks. Although several insurers (including two new entrants to the marketplace) successfully bid to contract with the state, providers largely declined to join MBPO networks, resulting in limited MBPO availability. This was most likely because MBPOs cap aggregate provider payments at no more than 160 percent of Medicare reimbursement rates as its primary method of containing costs, while imposing no explicit cost reduction obligations on insurers.

To improve provider participation in subsequent years, Washington leveraged its market power and required providers that (voluntarily) participate in other state health insurance programs, including Medicaid, to join at least one MBPO network. While lawmakers were told this would have the same effect as a mandate, the legal and political optics may have been more palatable, as providers ultimately maintained a choice of whether or not to participate in state-aligned programs.Footnote 27 Indeed, this tactic is akin to how many private actors engage in health care markets (albeit subject to criticism as anticompetitive). For example, large health systems commonly negotiate all-or-nothing contracts with insurers, where the insurer must contract with all providers within the system or none at all. Washington’s tying requirement helped expand MBPO plan availability and enticed more insurers to bid to offer MBPO plans. The increased competition even allowed Washington to selectively contract with just a subset of insurers that offered the best mix of geographic reach and lower premiums.

Washington’s MBPOs are increasingly becoming the lowest premium options in the marketplace, but they still have not been able to achieve significant premium reductions and enrollment remains low. Looking ahead, market dynamics – and the political choices that shape them – will continue to affect how well Washington’s public option program will be able to reduce costs. The biggest test may be whether the MBPOs can attract consumers in substantial numbers while keeping prices in check. As with marketplaces, the American preference for choice may limit how much costs can be constrained with private market tools alone: Current MBPO plan networks are narrower than their competition, which has allowed insurers to negotiate lower reimbursement rates by promising greater volume to the limited number of in-network providers. But consumers may prefer to maintain their choice of provider or hospital even if it means paying more. Washington and other states implementing or considering MBPOs have to tread carefully and find the right balance between making the products competitive in the market and achieving cost containment.

6.3.3 State Employee Health Plans

State Employee Health Plans present one of the biggest opportunities for states to contain health care costs by engaging with, rather than regulating, the market. State employee health plans have significant purchasing power: State and local governments are frequently the biggest employer in a given state and administer an employee benefit program. State employee health plans also have a direct interest in reducing spending on employees’ health care services – amplified by the frequent threat of state budget cuts. But unlike other employer health plans, SEHPs often cannot achieve cost savings by shifting costs to their employees, due to legal and practical constraints.

State employee health plans contract with private insurers – either as a third-party administrator (TPA) or insurer – and these private insurers, in turn, negotiate rates with health care providers. The dynamics between these parties affect the success of any cost-containment initiative. Some SEHPs have leveraged their purchasing power in negotiations with both providers and TPAs to promote cost containment. For example, in 2016, Montana SEHP administrators used their purchasing power to cap what they would pay for hospital services at 234 percent of Medicare rates,Footnote 28 which saved the state about US$47.8 million over three years.Footnote 29 Additionally, at least fourteen states have leveraged their vendor procurement process to “extract[] performance guarantees and hold[] TPAs accountable to cost containment goals.”Footnote 30 For example, one study reports that a state implemented a “reverse auction” strategy when soliciting bids from their TPAs, sharing information about bids received with all competing vendors to encourage better offers in subsequent bidding rounds. The study finds that this state succeeded in lowering prices and increasing cost transparency.Footnote 31 These reforms have been possible because SEHPs’ captive enrollee population draws both providers and insurers to the negotiating table.

Cost-containment efforts by state administrators have been rare, however. In many cases, SEHPs are limited by their need for state legislative approval to pursue these types of cost-containment strategies, opening the door to industry opposition that can kill reform efforts or create loopholes.Footnote 32 For example, the New Jersey SEHP has legislative authority to use the above-mentioned “reverse auctioning” procurement strategy to get concessions from its pharmacy benefit managers, but not its TPAs.Footnote 33

Even when legislative authority is not a barrier, SEHPs still face an uphill battle when implementing reforms. State employee health plans are entrenched in decades-old traditions and policies, making it difficult for policymakers and many SEHP administrators to see SEHP agencies as agents of reform. State employee health plan administrators have limited resources at their disposal compared to other large private purchasers. Developing cost containment initiatives can be resource intensive: states that have tried to develop innovative provider payment models, like episode-based or bundled payments, have described it as “a ton of work.”Footnote 34 Third-party administrators have also made it difficult for SEHPs to access and use their own claims data, a prerequisite for developing new cost-containment initiatives. Even when the data is available, many SEHPs lack the staffing and funding to adequately analyze it.

And, as with our other examples, market consolidation and consumer preferences also significantly limit SEHPs’ negotiating power. Public employees expect generous benefit packages with broad provider networks and eye efforts to contain costs with skepticism, viewing money saved as a benefit that accrues to the state, not to them directly. Provider consolidation exacerbates this problem, as employees do not want to lose access to a dominant health system, tying the plan’s hands when negotiating rates with providers. Similarly, states with a dominant insurer cannot afford to lose access to their current TPA, making it difficult to fully leverage the state procurement process to reduce costs. Dominant providers and TPAs can also wield considerable political influence and financial resources. For example, North Carolina’s SEHP recently conducted a transparent and thorough process requesting proposals for a TPA, and selected Aetna instead of Blue Cross and Blue Shield of North Carolina (Blue Cross NC), which had been the TPA for over forty years.Footnote 35 Blue Cross NC is now directing significant resources toward trying to get this decision overturned.Footnote 36

Despite the barriers, given their captive market and relative size, SEHPs remain an opportunity for states looking to experiment with cost-containment initiatives without generating the political opposition inherent in the legislative process.

6.4 State Contracting as a Stopgap: Holding the Line for Broader Reforms

Implementing effective cost-containment reforms is an immense challenge. Above, we have shared examples of how a handful of states have leveraged their role as private actors and contracting entities to advance this goal. While regulatory efforts to control prices largely remain politically infeasible, these examples offer a potential path forward. However, these state contractual approaches are not a panacea.

Despite working within a private law framework governed by market forces, state contractual and market-based approaches to cost containment can be seen as being closely intertwined with exercises of legislative and regulatory authority. Indeed, state actors frequently require legislative authorization to use their market power, and this opens the door to opposition. Even though these strategies mirror those private actors commonly use, proponents of “free market principles” or small government may reject these efforts as a proxy for government regulation or fail to adequately fund state agencies to effectively implement them. Perhaps even more detrimentally, these efforts face opposition from well-funded industry actors who no more wish to feel meaningful competitive or market pressure from the government than regulation.

Nonetheless, experience to date suggests contractual approaches carry a much lower risk of legal challenge and obstruction than direct price regulation, and SEHP reforms appear to have particular support from conservative policymakers.Footnote 37

The more profound limitations on contractual approaches to cost containment is consolidation in US health care markets combined, perhaps ironically, with an intense desire to preserve consumer choice. Often the government does not have meaningful bargaining power because there are only one or two dominant insurers and/or health systems in the market. The consolidation in the health care market is resulting in a market failure, where prices and premiums keep increasing, and anticompetitive practices are rampant. Even when the market is not heavily consolidated, policymakers remain hesitant to leverage their negotiating power and exclude higher-cost options and thereby limit consumer choice. That a “faith in … consumer choice”Footnote 38 can hijack cost containment efforts is only made more questionable by the fact that consumers, universally, struggle to make informed, rational health care decisions.

This conclusion brings us back to where many economists and policy experts started: If consumer choice and market power cannot achieve meaningful price controls, then comprehensive rate regulation may be in order. But if the opportunity arises, states may want to try the mechanisms discussed, here, while Congress debates broader federal reforms. US health care reform has tended to be a story of incrementalism, and experiences like selective contracting by the Massachusetts and California health insurance marketplaces, introduction of a market-based public health insurance option by Washington, and Montana’s experimentation with capping provider reimbursement can serve as precursors to more significant changes. Under the right circumstances, these policies benefit enrollees and can even have modest spillover effects. In acting now with the tools available, states can not only benefit themselves but lay the groundwork and show support for Congress to tackle health care costs nationally.

7 Adaptation of Tort Law to Modern Health Care Delivery in the Restatement of Medical Malpractice

Mark A. Hall Footnote *
7.1 Introduction

Prior to the mid-1960s, with the advent of Medicare and Medicaid, health law looked predominantly to various sources of private law – principally branches of common law – to address major issues at the time. Naturally, that legal landscape has changed a great deal, but common law still undergirds many of the classic components of the field. This chapter explores the extent to which common law remains capable of adjusting itself to evolving structures and dynamics in health care finance and delivery. It does so in the particular context of medical liability.

As we begin the inquiry, it helps to recognize that common law has two core but conflicting, features: stability and adaptability. Stability arises through stare decisis. Adaptability is inherent in the judge-made quality of common law doctrine. As the landscape changes that gives rise to common law, so too can the judicial outlook that applies the law’s principles, generating not only different rulings under established principles but also revision of governing principles at both second-order and higher levels of conceptualization.Footnote 1 Such doctrinal evolution or revolution can be slow and fitful, but many successful examples can be given of this innate adaptability.Footnote 2 At the same time, the common law’s precedential inertia can create impatience among scholars, regulators, and reformers eager to modernize hidebound legal principles.

The American Law Institute’s (ALI or Institute) first-ever project to restate medical liability law provides a fitting occasion to explore these tensions and themes in the context of tort law’s application to medical care delivery. Tort law has been a principal focus of the ALI from its beginning a century ago.Footnote 3 This medical liability project arose at the concluding phase of the Institute’s quarter-century work to issue its third Restatement of Torts law. Previous Restatements addressed medical malpractice only briefly, as a leading example of a more general concept of professional liability, discussed in just a single section.Footnote 4 In solipsistic contrast, the Restatement of the Law Governing Lawyers devotes eleven sections to legal malpractice.

A review of various provisions reveals that judicially determined common law is capable, to some extent, of evolving with the health policy times; however, there are significant points of inertia that may be hindering useful health policy developments. Surveying this landscape may help lawmakers and public policy officials identify where regulatory nudges or overt overrides can be helpful in freeing up precedential logjams.

Medical malpractice law arose in the nineteenth century, at a time when medical care could be described in its best light as primitive.Footnote 5 Importantly, treatment relationships then were almost entirely dyadic (with just a single provider) and episodic, addressing primarily acute issues. Also, patients paid entirely out-of-pocket and providers delivered care mostly in noninstitutional settings, either at home or in the doctor’s office. As common law is expected to do, it reflected, and thus was premised on, these essential features. As I have written elsewhere, the private law features of health law in particular are especially adept at recognizing and responding to the essential features of illness, vulnerability, trust, professionalism, and other core attributes of health care delivery and finance.Footnote 6

Obviously, it greatly understates things to say that much has changed in medicine over the past 200 years. Thus, we might expect that critical doctrinal elements and principles have shifted dramatically over time. However, many or most of the core essentials of the medical enterprise – the ontological assault of illness, the vulnerability a treatment relationship entails, the complexity and unpredictability medical practice, the fundamental existential stakes of the enterprise – inhere in the human condition and thus remain true today. But, for essential features that are more contingent, the common law’s precedential inertia might stunt doctrinal evolution. The emerging Restatement of Medical Liability provides an opportunity to learn the extent to which these competing features of private law affect the Institute’s ability to bring coherence to the common law of medical liability.Footnote 7

7.2 The Treatment Relationship

When does a physician or other care provider enter the realm of medical professional responsibility? According to tort law, this occurs when the provider forms a treatment relationship, that is, begins to undertake the care of a patient. Undertaking care is the critical point at which a provider leaves the zone of generic negligence law, which holds actors responsible only for risks they create judged by a general reasonableness standard and assumes the more affirmative responsibilities defined by professional standards.

A treatment relationship’s timeline – its beginning and ending – is defined largely by contractual principles. Sometimes overt agreements to start or end a treatment relationship can be identified, but often they cannot. A physician simply starts to engage with a patient and then stops engaging, or they engage in ways that can be ambiguous as to the nature and scope of the engagement. Thus, the Restatement of Medical Malpractice begins by addressing the foundational contours of a treatment relationship.Footnote 8

At the threshold, one visible indication of common law adaptation is the modernizing of the rules around formation of the treatment relationship. Historically, courts have tended to apply what might be called a “hair trigger” test for relationship formation, by finding that contractual elements are met with only a slight indication of potential intent by the provider to assume responsibility. Thus, in various circumstances, courts have found that a treatment relationship formed when a patient made an appointment, or when a provider discussed the patient’s situation and needs only briefly, or only with a colleague.

The quick trigger approach stands in sharp contrast to lawyers undertaking client representation. Lawyers commonly consult with a potential client before launching representation, and that launch rarely occurs without an explicit understanding about its basic scope and terms.

When patients are sick and in need of immediate attention, there are obvious reasons to dispense with formalities. Recognition, however, that greater complexities and subtleties can legitimately arise in the modern setting, coupled with the emergence of a more overtly “consumerist” ethos in medicine, led the Restatement to endorse a moderating stance. Based on limited, but sufficient, case law, the Restatement advises that, “in appropriate nonemergency circumstances, medical providers should have leeway, similar to that in legal representation, to first assess a patient’s condition and to discuss potential courses of treatment and costs before initiating a patient-care relationship.”Footnote 9 That passing sentence is a small but instructive example of common law adaptation.

The unhelpful aspect of inertia in the common law can be seen, however, in its episodic conception of treatment relationships. Following well-established case law, the Restatement declares that a treatment relationship ceases “once the particular condition or conditions that gave rise to treatment no longer need attention, unless the patient has reason to believe that the provider intends to continue the relationship.” As it notes, this “captures what is sometimes referred to as a ‘spell of illness’ demarcation of treatment relationships.”Footnote 10 The Comment acknowledges, however, that “patients as well as providers often think of themselves as having an established and ongoing relationship that bridges episodes of illness.”

Here, the Restatement urges courts to better adapt the law to modern practice. The Comment instructs that medical liability law should attempt “to shape itself to the actual contours of patient-provider interactions and understandings.” Further, it notes that “several modern developments support, in appropriate circumstances, embracing a more continuous rather than episodic conception of patient-care relationships.” An obvious example is chronic illness with episodic flare-ups. Another, which is more institutionally contingent, is the contemporary emergence of primary-care “medical home” arrangements, “in which a primary-care provider is paid to manage a patient’s needs on an ongoing basis across a range of providers and conditions.” The Comment prompts courts to recognize that these (or similar) arrangements “can form an ongoing patient-care relationship that transcends spells of illness.”Footnote 11

This type of small-bore, stepwise evolution is a hallmark of the common law and thus is comfortably within the bounds of the Institute’s guidelines and practices for how Restatements justifiably may guide further legal development.Footnote 12 The Restatement embraces a similarly less transactional and more relational view in its section on informed consent. There, it keys the informed consent duty to a “course of treatment” rather than to a specific intervention, recognizing (again without much explicit precedent) that “it is typical, and permissible, to obtain informed consent in a manner that bundles a variety of discrete items of treatment.”Footnote 13 In these several respects, we see a somewhat successful, but still limited, ability of common law to adapt to basic changes in treatment relationships.

7.3 Sharing Responsibility among Medical Professionals

Common law has been somewhat less successful, however, in adapting to changes in how medicine is practiced. Tort law has frequently had to determine the scope of an individual provider’s professional responsibility in the context of multiple professionals working together as part of a treatment team.Footnote 14 This first arose in the surgical operating arena. Cases a century ago asked whether a surgeon is responsible for errors that surgical assistants make, such as nurses charged with counting sponges to ensure none are left behind. As surgical techniques advanced, subsequent courts were asked to determine a lead surgeon’s responsibility for another physician’s error in, for instance, administering anesthesia.Footnote 15

Initially, courts adopted a strong version of vicarious liability known as the “captain of the ship” doctrine, which held the lead surgeon responsible as a matter of law for any negligence under their “command,” regardless of the surgeon’s actual control over the team member.Footnote 16 One rationale at the time for this small-scale form of enterprise liability was that, with respect to nurses, if the surgeon were not liable then there would be no adequately sized pocket from which to seek recovery, given that almost all hospitals at the time were immune from liability, either as charitable or governmental institutions.

In many cases, modern courts have appropriately backed away from this literal-absolutist application of the captain-of-the-ship metaphor, in favor of a more fact-based inquiry, now referred to as the borrowed “employee” doctrine.Footnote 17 This modern version appropriately adapted to changing circumstances in the profession and applies more conventional vicarious liability principles to inquire whether a surgeon, in a particular situation, controls, or has the right to control, “the manner and means” by which a colleague performs their work. Recognizing that in modern practice, the training and oversight of nurses is typically the hospital’s responsibility, this more nuanced doctrine nevertheless allows a finding based on the facts of a particular case that a surgeon assumed temporary control of a team member’s action.

But the story isn’t all a positive one. Variability remains in how these principles play out in recurring scenarios, including the original scenario of sponges, clamps, or other foreign objects accidentally left behind during surgery.Footnote 18 Some courts look to how providers themselves allocate responsibility, recognizing that “operating room personnel have specialized tasks to perform during surgery, … [and] that it [may] not [be] practical for [surgeons] to exercise control of the nurses in their sponge-counting task.”Footnote 19 Other courts, however, continue to hold surgeons responsible as a matter of law.Footnote 20 They do so without resuscitating an explicit and free-ranging captain-of-the-ship notion; instead, they embrace the more limited common-sense notion that when a surgeon inserts a foreign object, the surgeon remains responsible for ensuring its proper removal. That line of thinking is more appropriately considered to be a straightforward recognition of a nondelegable duty.Footnote 21

These established strands of doctrine have not matured, however, into more general principles of shared professional liability when errors occur in team-based care settings. The Reporters’ Note to the Comment on borrowed employees explains that, “[a]lthough such team-care arrangements are increasingly common, courts continue to resist viewing them as a basis for vicarious liability among individual medical professionals, as long as none of the providers actively supervises or controls his or her counterpart. Instead, courts apply a highly compartmentalized view of shared physician responsibility.” The Note continues in an editorial vein to say:

This highly compartmentalized view is subject to the criticism that it fails to reflect the increasing emphasis in modern medicine on caring for patients through coordinated teams, as seen, for instance, in the rise of “accountable care organizations” and “care coordination teams” based with multidisciplinary primary care medical homes that monitor and coordinate care patients receive from a range of providers.Footnote 22

These sentiments are those only of the Reporters, however, and do not speak for the Institute. The ALI’s official position is expressed in Comments recognizing that “much of this Restatement addresses a simple one-on-one relationship between provider and patient, even though much medical care, especially in hospital settings, is in fact provided by teams that share and assign responsibilities in complex ways,” and noting that the “Restatement only partially accounts for this complexity.”

Here, then, we see a glaring example of the limits of common law tort principles, rooted in an anachronistic framing of medical care delivery. Despite dramatic changes in how modern medicine structures care delivery, tort law can struggle to fully adapt to modern conditions.

Partly accounting for this doctrinal rigidity, however, is that medical professionals themselves hold on to a bounded view of their own responsibilities. Thus, when providers collaborate across disciplines or fulfill supervisory roles, they form explicit understandings about the nature of limits of their separate but dovetailing responsibilities.Footnote 23 In honoring these understandings, tort law is not so much stubborn to change, as it is compliant with professional norms. Thus, the common law is more subject to the criticism of declining to push for overarching structures of responsibility, than of failing to recognize professional and institutional realities.Footnote 24

7.4 Institutional Responsibility

Common law’s rigidity can be seen in the failure of institutional liability to fully adapt to modern circumstances. A few years before work began on the Third Restatement of Torts, the Institute commissioned a project, led by a group of eminent torts scholars, to restate institutional responsibility for personal injury. The group’s work proved too scholarly and lacked grounding in existing case law. The Institute therefore downgraded what was originally intended as a Restatement to simply a “Reporters’ Study,”Footnote 25 meaning that it spoke only for the reporters and not the Institute.Footnote 26 For similar reasons, this Restatement attempts no bold move toward sweeping enterprise liability for medical institutions.Footnote 27 That move would require fairly dramatic legislation action. Short of that, however, this Restatement recognizes a number of doctrinal advancements that, potentially, form building blocks for more sweeping enterprise liability.

First, the Restatement’s institutional liability ambit is substantially broader than just hospitals and nursing homes. The institutions subject to some form of medical liability are “entities that arrange for or furnish medical care through the services of medical professionals,” including: “medical facilities that treat patients, such as hospitals, clinics, and nursing homes; entities, such as managed care insurance plans, that arrange medical care for their customers; and newly emerging arrangements such as ‘accountable care organizations.’”Footnote 28 This Section is explicit, however, that all such institutions do not have the same set of duties. Instead, different duties apply according to whether the institution directly delivers care or instead merely helps to arrange for care.

Ample precedent exists to articulate the basic duties owed by institutions engaged in direct medical care. Precedent is limited, though, for other forms of institutions – those that merely arrange for or influence patient care rather than act as a provider. Managed care insurers are the primary example, but, owing to preemption by the Employee Retirement Income Security Act (ERISA), relevant precedents are scarce.

Despite this absence of precedent, the Section is able to state based on general principles that any such medical institution owes a “duty of reasonable care” to the extent that it “select[s] and retain[s] the medical professionals who furnish care under its auspices,” or that it “make[s] or actively review[s] medical decisions.”Footnote 29 Comments explain that this structure and wording does not require institutions to engage in such activities unless they actually deliver care; if not, the Section tailors medical duties to the functions that particular institutions choose to undertake.Footnote 30 These principles provide appropriate room for flexible development both of different types of medical institutions and different attendant duties, rather than embracing a “one size fits all” rule.

The Institute is especially careful to avoid insisting that medical institutions actively supervise medical professionals in a manner that requires institutions to regularly inject themselves directly into medical decision-making as it occurs (rather than reviewing decisions more retrospectively). If institutions choose to do so, naturally they assume a more exacting duty of care, but requiring institutions to take on this responsibility would contravene public policies that seek to minimize untoward institutional influence in professional judgment. In these ways, the Section aims to set a doctrinal stage for the ongoing development of a wide variety of different types and forms of medical institutions.

The Restatement also addresses institutional liability through vicarious liability doctrine. In particular, the Restatement discusses the substantial body of case law that has developed under the “apparent (or ostensible) agency” doctrine.Footnote 31 In developing and applying this and other aspects of vicarious liability, the Comments emphasize that courts are especially attentive to public policy consideration, such as:

(1) patients’ reasonable understandings about who is responsible for their care; (2) medical professionals’ and institutions’ reasonable understandings about how roles and responsibilities are assigned, shared, and allocated; and (3) society’s broader interest in promoting safe, efficient, and high-quality care.Footnote 32

Because these policies can point in different directions or can be given differing weights, there is notable variability in the extent to which different courts, sometimes from the same jurisdiction, assess whether an adequate manifestation of authority exists to invoke institutional vicarious liability.

Nevertheless, the Restatement is explicit that doctrinal articulation and application of vicarious liability should change in response to changes in health care delivery and finance. Thus, Comments note that the classic model – of independent physicians on a hospital medical staff having no other contractual relationship with the hospital – no longer predominates. Instead, physicians who treat hospital patients increasingly either work for the hospital or are part of a group that contracts, or is affiliated, with the hospital or a parent organization. Legal precedents from the pure independent-practice era may not necessarily be a good fit with these more complex “integrated delivery systems.”Footnote 33

Institutional liability for hospital-based specialists that a hospital does not employ is the leading example of doctrinal evolution that reflects several of these public policy considerations. Conventionally, when a professional (or other actor) is not an actual employee or agent of an institution, the institution assumes no vicarious liability unless the injured party (here, a patient) detrimentally relies on the institution representing that the professional is acting on its behalf as its agent.Footnote 34 Courts increasingly have relaxed these doctrinal demands of actual reliance and overt representation. They have held, for instance, that patients need not show reliance in the form that a different understanding about agency would have caused them to seek care elsewhere. Instead, patients need only show simply that they assumed the doctor was working for the hospital. Moreover, in many jurisdictions, patients need not point to a specific holding out or representation of agency; instead, it suffices that the patient’s assumption was reasonable in the circumstances.

The Restatement makes ample room for these doctrinal liberalizations but does not insist on their adoption, recognizing that doing so appropriately requires taking account of factual circumstances. Noting the variability that remains among decisions, as well as the fact-sensitivity of these standards, the relevant Comment sets an outer limit of apparent agency only at the point where “a patient establishes a relationship with an independent physician prior to hospital treatment.”Footnote 35 Then, “the patient cannot convincingly claim that the independent physician is the hospital’s apparent agent, simply because the physician is on the hospital’s medical staff or is entitled to work on the hospital’s premises.” Otherwise, for hospital-based specialists, “various circumstances can give rise to a patient’s reasonable belief that the physician is acting and has authority to act on behalf of the hospital when, in fact, the physician is an independent contractor.”Footnote 36

Beyond this expansion of apparent agency, tort law has not gone much further toward possible full-scale enterprise liability for hospitals or other medical institutions, nor does this Restatement encourage doing so, recognizing that Restatements are not an overt law-reform initiative.Footnote 37 In this respect, basic institutional liability remains much as it was a half-century ago. It remains to be seen whether dramatic innovations such as artificial intelligence – allowing much more detailed real-time interaction with professional decision-making – will push institutional roles and legal doctrine to a tipping point of more encompassing liability.

In the meantime, this Restatement does contain limited doctrine that may become seeds for future development of more encompassing enterprise liability. It notes that, in emergency room settings, where public policy considerations loom especially large, more courts are willing to curtail or dispense with the factual issues that might complicate a finding of apparent institutional agency. These courts, for instance, tend to adopt a presumption of reasonable impression of agency status, and they decline for obvious reasons to honor disclaimers of agency contained in form paperwork presented to emergency patients.

The relevant Comment takes an important further step, pointing courts to the availability of a more straightforward, but still limited, embrace of nondelegability as a matter of law. Building from decisions that presume apparent agency, the Comment notes that, “for certain core hospital functions, such as nursing care, it may be unacceptable as a matter of law to permit a medical institution to disavow vicarious liability for the negligence of independent contractors – even if it furnishes patients clear and timely notice of the contractors’ independent (nonemployee) status.”Footnote 38

The extent to which courts take up this invitation remains to be seen. But, even with some uptake, wholescale enterprise liability for independent physicians remains inconceivable in the short or medium term. More likely, continuing integration among facilities and professionals will diminish the practical importance of any major doctrinal reform regarding independent physicians.

7.5 Conclusion

This chapter presents several examples of tort law’s ability to thoughtfully adapt to changes in health care delivery at a measured pace – a pace that does not attempt to anticipate changes before they become widespread but also does not lag too terribly far behind important changes. The new Restatement of Medical Malpractice dutifully reflects where such changes have already taken hold and points to other changes that are primed to occur or to become more mature. Considering how rapidly health care delivery has changed, tort law appears by this assessment to be performing acceptably well on the adaptability score.

In some respects, however, this assessment highlights challenges to tort law governing and shaping modern health care delivery. Because the DNA of tort law adapts to practices, structures, and norms as they are, it is not well suited to leading or pushing for reform. Because a Restatement is, at its core, a synthesis of existing doctrine rather than a law-reform enterprise, Restatements have very limited ability to force tort law to improve or modernize. Nevertheless, embedded in the Restatement are a number of key passages that point in potentially constructive directions that future evolution of tort doctrine might take. Other points of doctrinal rigidity, however, might require more overt law-reform efforts to overcome.

8 Pandemic Harms and Private Law’s Limits A Proposal for Tort Replacement

Jill R. Horwitz , Alberto De Diego-Habel , and Daniel B. Rodriguez
8.1 Introduction

In the early days of the COVID-19 pandemic, many people predicted a flood of tort litigation against commercial businesses by individuals alleging negligent exposure to the virus.Footnote 1 Although negligently caused injuries almost certainly occurred, the flood of litigation never materialized.Footnote 2 In part, the small number of claims can be explained by many states’ efforts to avert economic disaster by immunizing businesses.Footnote 3 But the private law of tort itself also proved a formidable barrier, particularly given the difficulty of establishing causation in this context. This absence of tort claims may well have helped businesses ranging from residential health care providers to restaurants, as well as the economy and social life more generally. But the dearth of claims almost certainly left a great number of negligently injured parties without recourse or compensation to address their devastating harms.

The case of the pandemic suggests that traditional private law tools ordinarily available to address negligently caused harms – civil tort claims that leave it to private parties to litigate over whether the victim or the wrongdoer will bear the financial burden of wrongdoing – were poor legal tools for the job. An obvious response would be to adjust tort law standards to ease the path toward recovery under a private system, but this approach to addressing the need for compensation would risk the flood of litigation that observers were worried about in the first place.

We propose that a publicly administered tort-replacement scheme could have done a better job. Most obviously, it would have done a better job compensating negligently injured victims who otherwise received no compensation. Moreover, a carefully designed system of tort replacement might have provided such compensation without sacrificing (much of) the deterrence that tort law, albeit imperfectly, often provides. In other words, with appropriate regulation, tort replacement can address the twin goals so commonly associated with private law tort: compensation and deterrence.

In fact, as we explain below, the government has historically replaced the private law of tort with a publicly administered system to address analogous problems to those raised by the COVID-19 pandemic. Recognizing that this pandemic will neither be the last crisis nor even the last pandemic that will raise the need for unmet financial burdens to negligently injured victims, we can learn from this history.

Section 8.2 explores the limits of applying private tort law to the COVID-19 transmission context, limits we suggest could apply to pandemics and other emergencies more generally. Section 8.3 reviews past examples of the government replacing private tort law with a publicly administered compensation system. Section 8.3.1 highlights two instances in which tort replacement was used primarily to facilitate access to compensation, whereas Section 8.3.2 highlights instances in which tort replacement was used to prevent a flood of litigation. Taken together, these examples suggest that replacing tort (rather than loosening doctrinal barriers to recovery in court or erecting new ones in the form of liability shields) is the right solution in this context. In Section 8.4 we set out a brief discussion of how public law can be used to supplement, or even supplant, private law to fill the needs left by private law to set out the substantive claim. Section 8.5 considers objections, and Section 8.6 concludes.

8.2 The Pandemic Liability Dilemma: Individual Compensation versus Economic and Social Disruption

The COVID-19 pandemic harmed people around the world. In the United States alone, nearly 1.2 million people died because of the virus, and many more suffered serious, often permanent injuries.Footnote 4 The economic loss has been massive as well, with some estimates at US$14 trillion by the end of 2023.Footnote 5 Some of the spread of the disease was caused by individual negligence; some was caused by businesses, including health care businesses, such as nursing homes, that failed to take appropriate precautions to reduce the risks of spreading disease.

Although many victims of COVID-19 had health insurance or other forms of insurance to cover some of the financial costs of their injuries, many did not. Private insurance, as others have pointed out,Footnote 6 has proved inadequate to handle most business- and health-related losses. For those who became infected in the workplace, workers’ compensation was not available for the spread of disease in many jurisdictions. Many victims of negligently transmitted COVID-19 who were otherwise uncompensated needed immediate relief to pay for ongoing medical care, time off work, and other harms.

In theory, private tort law could provide that relief. Consider a hypothetical case of COVID-19 transmission vis-à-vis the elements of a conventional tort: (1) Injuries in the form of death, disability, treatment costs, and lost wages are all obvious consequences of COVID-19 transmission; (2) businesses owe duties to employees, customers, patients, and others to whom they could cause harm by failing to adopt reasonable precautions to prevent the spread of COVID-19; (3) businesses might breach these duties by failing to adopt such reasonable (even statutorily required) precautions; and (4) both actual and proximate cause could theoretically be established, such as where an employer knew or should have known that an employee was likely infected yet required her to come to work. Some combination of these circumstances could establish a case for damages.

In practice, however, COVID-19’s characteristics pose roadblocks to the prima facie case, particularly the element of causation. Contact with any person – while shopping, filling a car with gasoline, interacting with a neighbor, or even visiting outside – raises the possibility of exposure. Thus, unless the facts line up just so or reliable DNA sequencing is applied to trace transmission – both of which are unlikely – it is nearly impossible to establish causation by a preponderance of the evidence. Tort law thus proves an ineffective mechanism for compensating injured individuals in this context. And given the nature of infectious diseases more generally, this is likely to be true in the context of future pandemics as well.

One answer to address all this uncompensated suffering is to conceive of it as an accident and allow loss to “lie where it falls.”Footnote 7 But to the extent that such losses were caused by negligent behavior, it would seem unfair to leave victims without recourse for this but not other wrongs, particularly given the extent of the suffering. Moreover, there are strong policy reasons for extending coverage via tort replacement to those victims who are not eligible for other forms of relief. As we have seen through this and earlier pandemics, the more serious and sustained the human suffering, the greater the threat to our economy and social life. Indeed, we can recall in the early months of the COVID-19 pandemic the profoundly unsettling tableaux of empty streets, unattended funerals and religious gatherings, and the sudden paucity of normal human connection that accompanied the draconian steps to stop the spread of the virus.

Yet even if the causation problem could have been solved by better tracing, it is not obvious that widespread tort liability for negligent COVID-19 transmission would have been any more desirable than tort replacement during the pandemic or that it would be during the next pandemic. After all, even if plaintiffs could overcome these proof challenges (as well as other challenges such as liability shields and workers’ compensation restrictions), the enormous costs for businesses (especially small ones given what would be untenably high insurance costs), the economy, and the judicial system might not be worth the benefits to victims.

Similarly, the potential negative effects of tort on social life, such as more widespread quarantines and shutdowns, might be catastrophic. A public tort-replacement system may provide an answer.

8.3 Lessons from Prior Examples of Tort Replacement

Unlike COVID-19, the liability dilemma posed by the virus is not novel. In the past, legislatures have adopted administrative compensation schemes to (1) meet the needs of potential plaintiffs who face substantial obstacles to recovery under the conventional tort system and (2) avoid excessive costs to defendant businesses, industries, the economy, and social order that could result from reforming tort to allow mass recoveries.

8.3.1 Meeting the Unmet Needs of Potential Plaintiffs

Here, we consider two examples of administrative solutions that legislatures have offered in the past that provide a useful analogy to COVID-19:

8.3.1.1 The Federal Black Lung Compensation Scheme

Following a deadly explosion at a mine in West Virginia in 1968, Congress passed the Federal Coal Mine Health and Safety Act, including Title IV, the Black Lung Benefits Program.Footnote 8 Congress designed the program to compensate coal miners suffering from black lung disease and address the lack of benefits for inactive miners and their survivors.Footnote 9

As in the COVID-19 context, injured miners had difficulty establishing a tort claim, and workers’ compensation was not generally viable. State administrative programs tended to exclude occupational disease,Footnote 10 and injuries often emerged from symptomless exposure, taking the form of long-term and unpredictable respiratory disorders that were hard to identify within the statutes of limitations.Footnote 11

Congress’ first attempt to aid miners faltered. Despite Congress creating two rebuttable presumptions to assist claimants – that (1) the disease “arose out of the[ir] employment” and (2) the death was a direct result of the diseaseFootnote 12 – claimants continued to struggle with the statute’s causation requirements for reasons similar to why they struggled to establish causation under tort law, namely the amount of time between exposure and illness and the unpredictable nature of the disease. In 1972, Congress loosened the tort-like requirements to expand eligibility for benefits, such as by allowing surviving spouses to demonstrate only that at death the miner “was totally disabled due to black lung disease,” rather than that the miner’s death was the result of the disease.Footnote 13 The Act provides a useful example of a legislative solution when potential plaintiffs are unable to establish causation or access workers’ compensation benefits.

8.3.1.2 The Federal Nuclear Worker Compensation Program

In 2000, President Clinton issued an executive order recognizing the thousands of Americans exposed to nuclear radiation who developed “disabling or fatal illnesses” while building America’s nuclear defense.Footnote 14 Like black lung victims, these potential plaintiffs faced significant evidentiary hurdles in recovering under tort particularly with respect to causation “because of long latency periods, the uniqueness of the hazards to which they were exposed, and inadequate exposure data.”Footnote 15

In 2000, Congress passed the Energy Employees Occupational Illness Compensation Program Act (EEOICPA), which confers on the Department of Labor the primary responsibility of administering the compensation programFootnote 16 and provides cash compensation for medical expenses to workers and survivors “who contracted certain diseases as a result of exposure to beryllium, silica, or radiation while working for [the Department of Energy], its contractors, or subcontractors in the nuclear weapons industry.”Footnote 17 Although EEOICPA presents a different reason for tort replacement than the pandemic scenario – the government employed the injured workers and, therefore, stood in the role of the tortfeasor, whereas in the COVID-19 case the government would provide relief to victims harmed by others – the example remains relevant insofar as the government stepped in to compensate injured parties who needed relief but were unable to show causation or access workers compensation. Some level of deterrence may have been preserved during the shift from private tort law to administrative tort replacement, given the dual role of the government as both the administrative payer and the tortfeasor.

8.3.2 Harms to Industry, the Economy, and Society

One way to meet the needs of frustrated, would-be tort plaintiffs would be to loosen the causal requirements of tort law so that those plaintiffs can bring claims. Such a reconfiguration of tort law, however, would introduce the problem that so many worried about at the start of the pandemic: The costs of defending all claims and satisfying judgments in successful claims would harm certain industries and the economy more generally. As with the compensation problem discussed above, tort replacement has been employed to solve the problem of expected harms being too widespread and the costs imposed on defendants being too high. Here we review two examples of tort-replacement schemes established to protect the public interest by shoring up an industry or service – those for 9/11 victims and for neurologically impaired infants. We then briefly consider workers’ compensation, the most salient example of tort replacement.

8.3.2.1 The 9/11 Victims Compensation Fund

Congress enacted the Air Transportation Safety and System Stabilization Act both to compensate 9/11 victims via the US$7.375 billion Victims’ Compensation Fund and to prevent devastation to the airline industry and its insurers from flight stoppages, decreased demand, and tort litigation.Footnote 18 Although the former purpose is more well-known, the preamble to the Act describes it as “[a]n act to preserve the continued viability of the United States air transportation system.”Footnote 19 The Act provided air carriers with US$5 billion in direct grants for losses incurred due to the attacks,Footnote 20 up to US$10 billion in loan guarantees,Footnote 21 and, as amended, precluded compensated victims from filing claims,Footnote 22 capped damages in cases against airlines by plaintiffs not eligible for or otherwise participating in the Fund,Footnote 23 and capped liability for other types of industry participants such as aircraft manufacturers, airport owners, and governmental entities.Footnote 24

Potential 9/11 and COVID-19 plaintiffs faced some similar challenges; namely, identifying the tortfeasor (the negligent COVID-19 transmitter or the terrorist organization) was difficult if not impossible. And the airlines – like many businesses in the COVID-19 context, particularly smaller ones – faced potential damages amounts far exceeding insurance funds.Footnote 25

8.3.2.2 No-Fault Medical Malpractice: Neurologically Impaired Infant Programs

The American medical malpractice system has long been criticized as imprecise and unjust, largely ineffective at addressing the high rate of medical errors in the medical system.Footnote 26 In brief, “only a small fraction of those injured by medical negligence ever bring a claim; those who do sue may face years of litigation before they recover; and much of the money spent on malpractice litigation goes to cover its costs rather than to compensate the victims of malpractice.”Footnote 27 And what these deficiencies reveal, apropos of the larger dialogue of the book of which this chapter is a part, is the often intrinsic difficulties of using classic tort law remedies to accomplish wider social aims, be they deterring bad behavior while maintaining an optimal level of social activity or, returning to our central focus, providing adequate compensation to redress harm.

No-fault malpractice – a system under which an administrative body awards compensation for medical injuries based on a predetermined, standardized schedule – garnered considerable attention in the 1990s and early 2000s.Footnote 28 For example, in 2002, before becoming Administrator of the Centers for Medicare and Medicaid Services, Don Berwick wrote: “We badly need at least one courageous, time-limited experiment on a no-fault tort system at a statewide or regional level with enterprise-level responsibility for compensating victims of medical injury.”Footnote 29 Two states subsequently adopted (quite narrow) no-fault medical malpractice programs.

In response to insurers canceling obstetricians’ malpractice coverage and obstetricians’ subsequent threats of quitting, Florida and Virginia implemented tort-replacement programs for the families of severely injured newborns, the cases constituting the largest percentage and highest-cost obstetrical claims.Footnote 30 These programs provide compensation in the form of medical, rehabilitation, nursing care, and other expenses for categories of newborns who suffer particular iatrogenic harms, regardless of whether the cause of the harm was negligent.Footnote 31 The programs were primarily designed to prevent an exodus of medical providers,Footnote 32 and they largely worked. Hospitals and physicians participate in extraordinary numbers.Footnote 33 Whereas previously, obstetricians increasingly could not obtain medical malpractice liability insurance due to untenable cost, the programs took the most expensive cases out of the malpractice system, spread costs beyond obstetricians, and ultimately resolved the crisis.

8.3.2.3 Workers’ Compensation

Perhaps no administrative tort-replacement scheme is as well-known and long-standing as workers’ compensation. Until the mid-nineteenth century, the common law provided workers effectively no recourse to recover against their employers under tort for injuries suffered on the job.Footnote 34 The lack of recourse was grounded in an outdated notion that “an employee should be grateful for the opportunity for gainful employment … any special legal protection on top of his good fortune was quite unthinkable.”Footnote 35 As the law developed and workers began to win some tort claims, concerns about employer liability costs grew.Footnote 36

Based on the Prussian system of workers’ compensation,Footnote 37 which offered benefits and compensation for “job-related injuries and medical care and rehabilitation…” and precluded employees from suing their employers, states began adopting comprehensive workers’ compensation laws in the 1920s.Footnote 38 By 1948, every state had adopted some form of this no-fault insurance, a move that was largely motivated by the need to mitigate a broad threat to the economy, one similar to the economic paralysis that has often accompanied pandemics in the past and present.

8.4 A Brief Proposal and Policy Imperatives

Wrongs between private parties – whether in health care or outside – are typically adjudicated under private law. Yet, however coherent a system for deciding where the costs of accidents should fall generally, sometimes private law fails to realize either its own goals (e.g., compensation and aligning incentives) or important social goals. In such cases public law can supplement, or even supplant, private law to fill the needs left by private law.

Offering a full proposal is far beyond the scope of this short chapter. Instead, we have focused on two more modest aims. First, we suggest that tort replacement in the form of a social insurance-like compensation scheme might have solved some of the problems that private tort law failed to address during the pandemic and offers a policy solution for next time. Second, we offer multiple examples of effective use of tort replacement to solve compensation problems or, in the alternative, to forestall crushing litigation.

Importantly, we do not envision complete replacement but, instead, propose to supplement tort. For example, conventional tort should be available for cases involving any breach more culpable than negligent behavior, including grossly negligent, reckless, willful and wanton, and intentional behavior that causes harm. Moreover, we recognize the need to protect against the risk that tort replacement would effectively provide social insurance for all relevant harms, such as all COVID-19 transmission, and, thereby, lead to unsustainable costs. We, therefore, envision limiting the program in various ways, such as through subrogation rules that would only cover damages not otherwise covered through existing health insurance, unemployment coverage, business insurance, or other programs.

Tort replacement is worth considering in the pandemic or similar contexts for at least the following four overlapping policy reasons:

  • First, it would provide compensation more quickly and efficiently than tort law can likely do during the time of a pandemic. COVID-19 victims, for example, have faced great obstacles in maintaining a successful tort suit. To wit, they are not likely to establish causation, and even if they could, many defendant tortfeasors (namely, small businesses) would be effectively judgment-proof. With a replacement regime, these would-be plaintiffs could promptly receive the compensation they need to take care of health and other pressing expenses.

  • Second, equity and fairness favor tort replacement in these circumstances. More than in other mass tort settings, the facts often differ by case – the manner of exposure varies tremendously across and within industries. Consider the differences in congregate care settings, nursing homes, and college dorm rooms. With such different underlying facts, opportunities for class actions or other consolidated litigation are limited. Compensation schemes are likely to reach more potential plaintiffs and be more equitable across a range of plaintiffs and defendants than conventional tort law.

  • Third, a sensible administrative mechanism would provide greater certainty and finality for potential plaintiffs. It would also lead to less business disruption because businesses could plan for the fees they would need to pay to benefit from a replacement system, and they would not need to adjust business to avoid a potential and uncertain spate of claims, which happened not to arrive during this pandemic. Of course, the cost of this system would be deterrence. We would address this in two ways. As discussed above, we would maintain the tort system for cases that involve breaches based on more culpable behavior than ordinary negligence. And we would rely on accompanying regulation that required compliance with safety standards for a business defendant to benefit from the replacement system. Other regulations, potentially at all levels of government, might penalize defendants who did not adhere to specific standards of behavior. Establishing workable criteria for business conduct consistent with current scientific expertise would be both more effective and less turbulent than the behavior required as revealed through aggregated tort judgments.

  • Fourth, the vast majority of states immunized businesses from tort liability to encourage them to stay or reopen in the face of various uncertainties relating to insurance, liability, and other factors beyond their control. The impact on certain segments of the economy, such as restaurants and concert venues, has been massive, and it likely would have been worse without such immunity. However, the benefits of immunity in terms of maintaining and restoring commerce and social life came at a great cost. Tort replacement would have allowed victims to have some recourse. In terms of potential defendants, linking participation in a replacement system with adhering to safety standards, as some immunity statutes did, might have avoided some harm.

8.5 Potential Objections

A tort-replacement system raises a host of practical and theoretical considerations as well as federalism issues. We briefly consider some of the most salient objections to tort replacement in this context.

First, and perhaps the biggest objection, is that a compensation scheme might fail to motivate individuals and businesses to take adequate precautions to reduce risk. As we explained above, although no-fault might impede certain corrective actions, we believe a system can be developed to incentivize good behavior and deter bad behavior. Moreover, one should not overstate the deterrent effects of conventional tort law; since most claims predictably have little chance of success, they are unlikely to deter bad behavior.

The second is that replacing tort might undermine a morally centered conception of tort law and liability recovery. To over-simplify, scholars have argued that tort is fundamentally about addressing a wrong committed by a particular party against a particular party, and so it is important that the tortfeasor, not an anonymous fund, compensate the victim. Under the contrary view – where tort consists of a simple economic calculation based only on deterrence and compensation – it doesn’t matter that a victim is compensated by the responsible tortfeasor, as long as potential tortfeasors are deterred by the threat of penalty and victims are compensated.Footnote 39

Although this objection is theoretically important, the practical counterfactual matters. The moral case for tort law assumes that businesses’ misconduct will be redressed through litigation between parties. But as we’ve discussed, litigation in this context has been stymied. Moreover, insofar as it is very difficult to identify misconduct in the infectious disease context, unless we make the untenable assumption that the very fact of operating a business and not knowing the health status of customers or employees is negligent behavior requiring redress, these pandemic cases are not viewed well through the lens of morally condemnable action.

The third objection is that this short chapter has not grappled with important practical questions, perhaps chiefly funding needs, which could be very large. Importantly, we are not suggesting the establishment of a new entitlement but only a supplement to existing insurance systems. Applying subrogation rules and the like, we propose tort replacement only for individuals and small businesses that do not have adequate means through insurance or other resources to deal with the serious harms that COVID-19 or some future pandemic disease may cause. In evaluating schemes, and especially in doing the cost/benefit analysis integral to making sound regulatory choices, policymakers should consider the economic (and other) effects of not dealing effectively with the matter of damage and compensation.Footnote 40 So viewed, it is by no means clear that a scheme of the sort we describe is much more costly than doing nothing of the sort.

Finally, this chapter cannot adequately analyze the enormous and enduring issues of federalism and comparative institutional competence that tort replacement raises. On the one hand, as tort is traditionally state law, it may make good sense to pursue compensation reform at the state level. On the other hand, the characteristics of COVID-19-related injuries, beginning with the ineluctability of borders in controlling transmission and the national impact on public health and the economy, suggest that an effective compensation scheme might require national action. In any event, our suggestion to consider tort replacement does not depend on whether a scheme is enacted by Congress or the states, and any constitutional problems can and should be addressed in the structure of proposed legislation.

8.6 Conclusion

Rather than reforming private tort law to address the great needs caused by pandemics such as COVID-19, we have considered replacing it with a public system. Precedents for such replacement were motivated by issues we saw in this latest pandemic, namely (1) the unmet needs of potential plaintiffs and (2) the significant harms to social life and the economy that would result from reforming tort by relaxing the requirement to connect the injury with the commission of a wrong. These programs have been generally successful at addressing both issues and serve as models for the type of compensation scheme legislatures should consider adopting in the COVID-19 context and in the face of pandemics to come.

9 The Human Body Commons A Private Law Contribution for the Advancement of the Right to Health

Enrique Santamaría Echeverría
9.1 Introduction

For much of history, research results and scientific knowledge were considered a part of the public domain. Basic research, carried out by academic and other nonprofit institutions, was heavily financed by public funds and agencies, which generally required data deposit into public repositories.Footnote 1 However, around the 1980s, a push for privatization of researchFootnote 2 led to what has been termed the “enclosure of the mind”Footnote 3 and a resultant profit-driven culture around scientific research.Footnote 4

Biomedical research has been particularly affected by this process of privatization. Broadly speaking, biomedical research is a field of science that aims to develop tools (e.g., medicines, tests, vaccines, medical devices) that prevent and treat diseases. This type of research relies heavily on three different but connected types of resources: human biological materials (HBM), health data, and previous scientific knowledge.

In biomedical research, the epistemological shift, from a public domain-oriented conception of science and knowledge to a profit-driven research culture, has limited the advancement of knowledge and, consequently, the human right to health.

Historically, private law – through patents, licenses, other intellectual property mechanisms, contracts, and property rights – has been instrumental to privatization and commodification. However, a political and legal struggle to subvert the privatization of resources in biomedical research has emerged, based largely on the argument that bringing back scientific knowledge to the public domain may cause positive spillovers (e.g., innovation, economic value, and protection of human rights). The “idea of the commons” plays a pivotal role in this argument.

Private law and the commons in biomedical research are typically regarded as opposing concepts. While the traditional understanding of private law elicits notions of ownership, patents, and privatization, the imagery of the commons in biomedical research evokes opposing notions of open access to HBM, data, information, and knowledge.

However, these two approaches are not always mutually exclusive. Scientific practice has demonstrated how private law rules can enhance and protect the commons, while at the same time, encouraging innovation. This chapter therefore explores how private law, via the establishment of property rights, intellectual property, licenses, and other contracts, can serve to advance the right to health by reinforcing biomedical research anchored in the commons. In particular, it explores how the interplay between private law and the commons is instrumental in protecting and promoting individual and collective human rights, with particular emphasis on the right to health and health care and the right to enjoy the benefits of science and scientific progress. More specifically, it explores whether the traditional functions of private law’s institutional arrangements can be modeled, and if necessary, subverted, to develop commons on (health) data, HBM, and scientific knowledge (together “human body commons”).

9.2 Human Body Commons Entangled: Unraveling Genealogies and Typologies

The terms “commons” or “communing” elicit different meanings and are used differently by different bodies of literature and disciplines.Footnote 5 While the terminology may be similar, the normative foundations and objectives behind these strands of scholarship differ significantly. This difference has led to considerable confusion and misunderstanding of the concept of the commons. A clear disambiguation is therefore essential to understand the potential application of this concept to health data, HBM, and scientific knowledge.

This chapter focuses on two distinct, but intertwined, bodies of literature that have developed clear theories on the commons: (1) theories on open commons (OC) and the public domain;Footnote 6 and (2) the works on the Institutional Analysis and Development (IAD) framework for the governance of common pool resources (CPR),Footnote 7 as proposed by Elinor Ostrom and further developed and adapted to account for different types of commons and institutions for collective action.Footnote 8

The OC envisions an open commons with a symmetric freedom to operate. Nobody from an unidentified class of users can rely on the power of the State to restrict access to the resource (usually non-rival or partially congestible). In this sense, OC is conceptually located outside the property regime.Footnote 9 Common pool resources are bottom-up arrangements with clear rules of membership and access to a resource (characterized by high rivalry and low excludability).Footnote 10 From this perspective, CPR are commons inside, but property outside, as members can rely on the power of the State to prevent nonmembers from accessing the resources.

Despite their differences, both types of commons (OC and CPR) share the underlying assumption that state or market solutions for the governance of resources are not always sufficient, nor necessary.Footnote 11 Nonetheless, these two theories on the commons can offer a compelling normative underpinning for the de-privatized governance of science and knowledge.

Two related problems at the intersection of both types of commons make the case: (1) the problem of sharing and circulating the managed resources and (2) the problem of freeriding, reseeding the commons, and distributing its benefits.

These problems are particularly complex for the governance of the different resources within the human body commons. First, individual rights on informed consent, privacy, and data protection tend to limit the circulation and the repurposing (secondary uses) of data and HBM. This makes personal data and HBM highly excludable (i.e., the use of these resources by others without consent is very limited).Footnote 12 Second, HBM, (health) data, and scientific knowledge are different types of resources: While scientific knowledge and data are, in principle, non-rival intangible resources (i.e., many can use the same resource at the same time) provisioned in market, public, or social processes, HBM are naturally provisioned tangible rival resources (i.e., the use of HBM prevents simultaneous consumption by others).

Third, the material dimension of HBM makes them perishable, consumable, and prone to contamination. Human biological samples are often consumed after they have been analyzed and, if not, it is difficult to guarantee that the samples have not been altered after the first analysis, which would make them unsuitable for research. Fourth, these resources are circularly connected – HBM are necessary for the extraction of data, which in turn, together with other types of health and medical data, are the raw materials for the creation of scientific knowledge. The latter is an input for further innovation and a source of positive societal spillovers. The obvious consequence of this interdependence is that the enclosure and privatization of one of these resources negatively affects the existence of the other two, while opening them contributes to the growth of the value of the others.Footnote 13

Against this backdrop, the question is: How can OC and CPR be applied to the governance of the human body commons? Several specific theories have been put forward to make use of these overarching frameworks to govern the resources included under the umbrella term “human body commons”: knowledge, data, and HBM. These theories include medical knowledge commons,Footnote 14 genome or genomic commons,Footnote 15 and medical information commons.Footnote 16

Although these theories reach different conclusions,Footnote 17 their importance lies in their theorization of knowledge (and data) as a resource: (1) The fact that knowledge is cumulative makes sharing and creation inextricably related processes; (2) the intellectual products of the past are inputs for future products; (3) the non-rivalry and non-excludability of knowledge in abstracto lead its boundaries to be either artificially built (e.g., through patents) or derived from the embodiment of the knowledge resource (e.g., HBM containing data); and (4) the creation of knowledge depends on rivalrous inputs (e.g., time and money).

Through the analysis of commons-based initiatives of different scales and purposes, the next section examines how private law, by accounting for the aforementioned characteristics, can contribute to the further construction of the human body commons.

9.3 Private Law and Human Body Commons: Between Open Commons and CPR

Commons may be the result of a top-down regulatory approach or, on the contrary, may arise as a response to a legal system establishing a proprietary regime for the governance of a given resource. In the latter case, the commons are carved out of the background law, by using or subverting the legal tools disposed by that very same legal regime.

Contract law and contracts constitute a relevant legal tool for the construction of human body commons. Jerome Reichman and Paul Uhlir were perhaps the first ones to explore the idea of a contractually reconstructed scientific commons.Footnote 18 Their advancement constitutes, yet again, a response to the phenomenon of privatization of science and data taking place in the last two decades of the twentieth century in the United States. Precisely because of the cumulative and circular nature of knowledge, their analysis focused primarily on the deposit of data in publicly accessible databases. However, it did not include the sharing of HBM.

But building on their work, a combination of theory and practice may show how contracts can contribute to the construction of commons on HBM. Material transfer agreements, the Structural Genomics Consortium Open Trust Agreement, and data cooperatives serve as examples.

A material transfer agreement (MTA)Footnote 19 is a contract in which a provider and a recipient agree to the transfer of tangible research materials, including HBM, for the recipient’s use.Footnote 20 Beyond their importance in determining the intellectual property rights for provider and recipient, MTAs are also central to one of the core institutions in the collection, processing, and sharing of HBM: the biobank. Despite the many differences in types and purposes, from population to disease-specific, a biobank is essentially an organized collection of human biological samples and associated data for the purposes of present and future research.Footnote 21 Biobanks may rely on tailor-made MTAs or can adopt a standardized MTA to share the samples in their collection to researchers and institutions. However, depending on the type of MTA, the recipient of the materials may not be allowed to further share original or derived materials.

For this reason, several standardized MTA models have been developed to facilitate the transfer and sharing of biological materials beyond the first recipient. These models include the Uniform Biological MTA (hereafter UBMTA),Footnote 22 the Science Commons MTA,Footnote 23 and the Open MTA.Footnote 24

The first of these models, the UBMTA, was developed in the United States by the National Institutes of Health (NIH) in collaboration with other repositories.Footnote 25 Although it facilitated sharing materials by eliminating the need for lengthy or impractical negotiations between institutions, it was also limited to academic or nonprofit institutions and precluded both commercial uses and the further distribution of materials and derivatives.Footnote 26

To remedy this situation, the Science Commons MTA permitted, under certain circumstances, the commercial use of materials, but continued to prohibit their further distribution. To overcome this limitation, the Open MTA was designed. The Open MTA not only allows its use to for-profit and nonprofit entities alike but also permits the use for commercial purposes and the further distribution of materials and derivatives (including tissue samples). Its design was based on the principles of nondiscrimination, access, attribution, redistribution, and reuse.Footnote 27 Despite their differences, these standardized MTAs constitute essential tools to guarantee and facilitate redistribution of biological materials.

Moreover, because standard MTAs can be easily adopted, they also enable biobanks to integrate in wider biobank networks,Footnote 28 participating in that way as nods in an open and growing network of human body commons.Footnote 29

Although the use of MTAs to facilitate the construction of human body commons is not completely new, their use has highlighted some of the advantages of using private law to facilitate the commons. But there are also disadvantages to consider. First, if MTAs do not include clauses on how research results would return to the commons (the problem of reseeding the commons described above), MTAs may in fact contribute to the privatization of research instead of advancing its opening. Second, the limits of MTAs stem from their contractual nature: as contracts are, as a general rule, not enforceable against third parties,Footnote 30 it would be difficult for the original provider of the materials to start an action against a third party who received the materials from the recipient side of the MTA. In other words, MTAs are not very useful in enabling the circulation of materials and data under the same set of rules and limitations.

Perhaps because of this very reason, private law has also relied – beyond contract – on property law for the circulation of research materials and the promotion of open science. The case of the Structural Genomics Consortium (SGC) Open Science Trust Agreement (OSTA) provides an important example.

SGC is a charity registered in the United Kingdom, the mission of which is to accelerate research in new areas of human biology and drug discovery.Footnote 31 Unlike MTAs, in which a bilateral agreement is concluded between provider and recipient, the SGC OSTA is an agreement in which the recipient of the materials agrees to become a trustee of the research material.

According to the SGC’s website:

A trust such as the OSTA is a legal mechanism under which an appointed trustee takes legal possession of property but assumes a duty to use or manage that property to benefit certain beneficiaries, which can be third parties and/or the public. With the OSTA, unlike under an MTA, by becoming a trustee of SGC‐provided research material, a recipient is undertaking a specific duty to benefit the public through open science.Footnote 32

Some of the obligations of the trustee include (1) not seeking or enforcing intellectual property rights covering the material, which could deter or prevent others in the research community from using the material to further the public good, and (2) placing the research findings and data resulting from their work with the material into the public domain, which helps to accelerate discovery.

Furthermore, the trustee is permitted to disseminate “the material to other researchers who likewise agree to become trustees, thus expanding the community of researchers committed to open science for the public good.”Footnote 33

According to the SGC, the rationale behind such an agreement, instead of an MTA, for example, is that treating the materials, not as a proprietary good, but as a public one to be shared broadly, accelerates discoveries stemming from the use of the material. Although initially mandated (i.e., the investigator requesting the materials must become a trustee), further transfers to new trustees must happen on a voluntary basis.

While the OSTA was not specifically designed to share HBM,Footnote 34 one can envision ways to modify it and include the possibility of sharing materials of human origin.Footnote 35 More specifically, it would be possible at the point of collection of the materials, for example, via broad consent mechanisms, to enable circulation of materials that otherwise could not circulate freely. An alternative to consent mechanisms for the circulation of materials of human origin would be to devise a specific set of principles for which research on HBM without consent would be legally and ethically permissible.

In addition to contracts and property law, other private law instruments allow for the creation of institutions of collective action for the construction of the human body commons. Cooperative-based initiatives for the governance of health data are particularly interesting.

Health data cooperatives are associations of individuals under a cooperative structure for the collective governance of their individual health data for mutual benefit.Footnote 36

According to some cooperative models for the use of health data, when data are controlled by citizens themselves, potential value of data can be maximized, while at the same time guaranteeing the protection of the data subjects’ rights. Thus, one could think of models in which the storage and secure handling of data is overseen by a trusted entity: the cooperative (co-op). Users could purchase a membership certificate for an amount of money and use the co-op as a trusted repository.

Although the cooperative model was initially intended for genomic data, nothing prevents people from depositing all kinds of personal or health data, regardless of their origin (e.g., applications, wellness devices, and medical devices). In this way, the members of the cooperative would have the right to vote on decisions related to the benefits derived from the exploitation of their data by third parties.

Under this model, a pharmaceutical or medical technology company, for example, would pay a sum of money for the right to exploit the data that the members of the cooperative have decided to share, and could also, depending on the agreements adopted, deliver the results of the research to the accounts of the associates or to the cooperative. The economic benefits of the information that the cooperative obtains from the exploitation of the data could be reinvested in research programs or other types of projects of public interest.

Data cooperatives are a perfect example of a CPR that integrates different sorts of data and data sources for biomedical research.

MIDATA Genossenschaft (MIDATA), a Swiss health data cooperative, serves as a case in point. According to its articles of association,Footnote 37 MIDATA operates a secure IT platform for the processing and sharing of personal data, and in particular, health data. The cooperative makes the platform available to natural persons so they can use it to store and share their data as self-determining agents with the aim of supporting research purposes.

MIDATA promotes the collective interests of account holders by enabling the shared use of their personal data. Individual account holders can consent to data analysis and secondary use by third parties in return for economic compensation.Footnote 38

At this point, it becomes evident how data cooperatives, as a form of CPR, can successfully manage genomic and other types of health data, while at the same time reseeding the commons with the profits and research results arising from the use of pooled data.

MIDATA is also relevant from the point of view of managing privacy in the human body commons.Footnote 39 Although in this case, explicit informed consent is necessary for the processing and sharing of health data, it is possible to find other legal pathways to govern health data sharing and access for secondary uses. Moreover, although data cooperatives have not yet proliferated, it is very likely that an increase in their number will follow their legal recognition by the EU Data Governance Act.

9.4 Conclusion

From the analysis of theories on the human body commons and private law examples from biomedical practices, several conclusions can be derived: (1) It is necessary to integrate different types and sources of data, facilitating interoperability and data sharing; (2) due to the circular nature of knowledge and data commons, to build a human body commons, it is necessary to strike an equilibrium between the positive societal data sharing spillovers and data protection and other individual human rights; (3) HBM, and not only knowledge and data, must be integrated in the analysis; and (4) it is paramount to establish clear rules for the reseeding of the human body commons in such a way that the intellectual products of the past become the input for future knowledge.

Furthermore, because human body commons integrate different types of resources (i.e., HBM, health data, and scientific knowledge), a combination of different types of commons is necessary for its further construction and development: top-down Open Commons and carved-out Common Pool Resources commons. By way of explanation, public ordering solutions open the scope of the public domain for the creation of open human body commons, while private ordering solution create common property regimes.

New theories on data, which facilitate the repurposing and reuse of health data, would change the status of personal health data from highly excludable to non-excludable. In this sense, a jump from a CPR to an OC can be envisioned with the help of regulatory instruments, which allow to bypass consent for the use of data for the “common good.”

For HBM, the embodied resource of the human body commons, it seems difficult to imagine a fully open commons. However, private law has proven useful for the circulation and sharing of materials and associated data. Here, commons on HBM can be organized as multiple nodes (e.g., biobanks) of CPR connected to a wider mixed network of health data OC and CPR.

For scientific knowledge, it is necessary to guarantee that the developments and innovation derived from the use of OC and CPR in HBM and health data, return and reseed the commons in the forms of knowledge, benefit sharing, and money. This could be enabled by top-down regulation or by forms of collective action and negotiation (e.g., health data cooperatives) with data users and industry.

This chapter demonstrated how contracts, property, and other private law mechanisms may be used as vehicles for the governance of health research resources and health policy.

Such policy must develop a framework to avoid freeriding from actors using the commons, as well as a normative framework well-grounded in the promotion and protections of human dignity and human rights,Footnote 40 with specific reference to the right to health and the right to enjoy the benefits of science may be a good starting point.

Footnotes

5 Data Transparency, ERISA Preemption, and Freedom of Contract

* This is a truncated version of the essay. A fuller version of the essay is on file with the author.

1 29 U.S.C. § 1144(a).

2 Prudential Ins. Co. of Am. v. Nat’l Park Med. Ctr., Inc., 154 F.3d 812, 818 (8th Cir. 1998).

3 Erin C. Fuse Brown & Jaime S. King, ERISA as a Barrier for State Health Care Transparency Efforts, in Transparency in Health and Health Care in the United States: Law and Ethics 304–05 (Holly Fernandez Lynch et al. eds., 2019); Craig Konnoth, Health Data Federalism, B.U. L. Rev. 2169, 2187–89 (2021); Craig Konnoth, Privatization’s Preemptive Effects, 134 Harv. L. Rev. 1937, 1961, 2207 (2021).

4 Gobeille v. Liberty Mut. Ins. Co., 577 U.S. 312, 323–24 (2016).

5 Pharm. Care Mgmt. Ass’n v. Gerhart, 852 F.3d 722, 728–30 (8th Cir. 2017).

6 Brown & King, supra Footnote note 3, at 308.

7 Stephen Barlas, Health Care Price Transparency Initiatives Are All the Rage: But Burgeoning Efforts Suffer from Myriad Shortcomings, 43 P&T 744 (2018).

8 Konnoth, Health Data Federalism, supra Footnote note 3.

9 Footnote Id. at 2189–90, 2205–10.

10 Colleen Becker, Digging into Prescription Drug Data: Affordability Boards and Transparency, Nat’l Conf. of State Legislatures (Oct. 26, 2022), https://www.ncsl.org/health/digging-into-prescription-drug-data-affordability-boards-and-transparency.

11 Brown & King, supra Footnote note 3, at 303–04.

12 No Surprises Act, 42 U.S.C. § 300gg-111(e) (effective Jan. 1, 2022).

13 Jack Hoadley et al., No Surprises Act: A Federal-State Partnership to Protect Consumers from Surprise Medical Bills, The Commonwealth Fund (Oct. 20, 2022), https://www.commonwealthfund.org/publications/fund-reports/2022/oct/no-surprises-act-federal-state-partnership-protect-consumers.

14 29 U.S.C. § 1144(a).

15 Pharm. Care Mgmt. Ass’n, supra Footnote note 5, at 729.

16 Gobeille, supra Footnote note 4, at 320 (quotation marks omitted).

17 Konnoth, Privatization’s Preemptive Effects, supra Footnote note 3, at 2204.

18 Footnote Id. Somewhat confusingly, the court held that ERISA also made “implicit” reference to ERISA by regulating PBMs, which provide services to ERISA plans.

19 Footnote Id. at 731.

20 Rutledge v. Pharm. Care Mgmt. Ass’n, 141 S. Ct. 474, 481 (2020).

21 Rutledge’s PBM regulation involved reimbursement standards and was therefore governed by N.Y. State Conf. Blue Cross & Blue Shield Plans v. Travelers Ins. Co., 514 U.S. 645 (1995), which had approved of such standards. Rutledge, supra Footnote note 20, at 480. But Gerhart’s regulation involved data transparency, and would be governed by Gobeille. Space limitations do not allow me to explain further.

22 Konnoth, Privatization’s Preemptive Effects, supra Footnote note 3, at 2204.

23 See, e.g., N.Y. State Conf. Blue Cross & Blue Shield Plans v. Travelers Ins. Co., supra Footnote note 21, 655 (“[i]f ‘relate to’ were taken to extend to the furthest stretch of its indeterminacy, then for all practical purposes pre-emption would never run its course”).

24 Footnote Id. at 2204–05; Konnoth, Privatization’s Preemptive Effects, supra Footnote note 3; Harris v. BP Corp. N. Am. Inc., No. 15 C 10299, 2016 WL 8193539, at *7 (N.D. Ill. July 8, 2016).

25 See Konnoth, Privatization’s Preemptive Effects, supra Footnote note 3, at 2208. As Respondent, the ERISA plan filed its briefs only after the US brief was filed. Space constraints prevent a full treatment of the argument.

26 See generally James W. Ely, Jr., Whatever Happened to the Contract Clause?, 4 Charleston L. Rev. 371 (2010).

27 Patricia McDonnell et al., Self-Insured Health Plans, 8(2) Health Care Fin. Rev. 12 (Winter 1986).

28 Thomas v. Marshall, 482 F. Supp. 160, 164 (S.D. Ala. 1979).

29 For example, van Boxel v. Journal Co. Emps. Pension Tr., 836 F.2d 1048, 1052 (7th Cir. 1987); Williams v. Rohm & Haas Pension Plan, 497 F.3d 710, 714 (7th Cir. 2007); Esden v. Bank of Bos., 229 F.3d 154, 173 (2d Cir. 2000); all argued that in pension contexts, ERISA was meant to eliminate freedom of contract.

30 See F. H. Buckley, Introduction, in The Fall and Rise of the Freedom of Contract 1–2 (F. H. Buckley ed., 1999) (noting how freedom of contract sentiments had returned to vogue since the 1970s).

31 Carland v. Metro. Life Ins. Co., 727 F. Supp. 592, 597 (D. Kan. 1989), aff’d, 935 F.2d 1114 (10th Cir. 1991).

32 Carland v. Metro. Life Ins. Co., 935 F.2d 1114 (10th Cir. 1991) (quoting cases with similar holdings).

33 Buce v. Allianz Life Ins. Co., 247 F.3d 1133, 1150 n.1 (11th Cir. 2001) (Barkett, J., concurring) (noting in a footnote “the limits the ‘savings clause’ imposes on an ERISA insurer’s freedom to contract”).

34 St. Francis Reg’l Med. Ctr. v. Blue Cross & Blue Shield of Kansas, Inc., 49 F.3d 1460, 1466–67 (10th Cir. 1995).

35 MBI Energy Servs. v. Hoch, No. 1:16-CV-329, 2016 WL 9307197, at *4 (D.N.D. Sept. 19, 2016).

36 In re UnitedHealth Grp. PBM Litig., No. 16-CV-3352, 2017 WL 6512222, at *14 (D. Minn. Dec. 19, 2017).

37 Gobeille, supra Footnote note 4, at 320–21 (emphasis added).

38 Pharm. Care Mgmt. Ass’n, supra Footnote note 5, at 728.

39 The countervailing concern is that network providers would not be incented to provide discounts if out of network providers could force their way into the network.

40 Elizabeth Rolph et al., State Laws and Regulations Governing Preferred Provider Organizations 47–48 (1986).

41 Petition for a Writ of Certiorari at 11, Ky. Ass’n Health Plans v. Miller, 538 U.S. 329 (2003) (No. 00-1471). While courts that uphold AWP statutes tend to conflate mandated provider laws and AWP laws, see Cmty. Health Partners, Inc. v. Com. of Ky., 14 F. Supp. 2d 991, 1000 (W.D. Ky. 1998), there are meaningful differences between the laws, see Express Scripts, Inc. v. Wenzel, 102 F. Supp. 2d 1135, 1150 (W.D. Mo. 2000).

42 29 U.S.C. 1144(b)(2)(A).

43 Ky. Ass’n Health Plans v. Miller, 538 U.S. 329, 341–42 (2003).

45 Footnote Id. at 339–40.

46 Sara Rosenbaum et al., Law and the American Health Care System 403 (2d ed. 2012).

47 CIGNA Healthplan of La., Inc. v. State, ex rel. Ieyoub, 883 F. Supp. 94, 96 (M.D. La. 1995), aff’d sub nom., CIGNA Healthplan of La., Inc. v. State of La. ex rel. Ieyoub, 82 F.3d 642 (5th Cir. 1996). In a previous case, a Virginia district court had invalidated an AWP law only to be overturned on appeal. Stuart Circle Hosp. Corp. v. Aetna Health Mgmt., 995 F.2d 500 (4th Cir. 1993).

48 CIGNA Healthplan, supra Footnote note 47, 883 F. Supp. at 96.

49 Express Scripts, Inc. v. Wenzel, 102 F. Supp. 2d 1135, 1147 (W.D. Mo. 2000), aff’d, 262 F.3d 829 (8th Cir. 2001).

50 Petition for a Writ of Certiorari at 5 n.2, Miller, 538 U.S. 329, (No. 00-1471) (“restrictions on petitioners’ freedom to contract with chiropractors”); Express Scripts, 102 F. Supp. 2d at 1147 (W.D. Mo. 2000) (“The alleged impact of H.B. 335 on ERISA plans is to eliminate their freedom to contract….”).

51 Stuart Circle, supra Footnote note 47, at 504–05.

52 Health Maint. Org. Ass’n of Ky. v. Nichols, No. CIV.A. 97-24, 1998 WL 34103663, at *7 (E.D. Ky. Aug. 6, 1998) (citation omitted).

53 Kentucky Ass’n of Health Plans, Inc. v. Nichols, 227 F.3d 352, 368 (6th Cir. 2000).

54 Footnote Id. at 370.

55 Footnote Id. at 380 (Kennedy, J., dissenting).

56 Robin Kar, Contract as Empowerment, 83 U. Chi. L. Rev. 759, 807 (2016); Gregory S. Alexander, Freedom, Coercion, and the Law of Servitudes, 73 Cornell L. Rev. 883, 903 (1988).

57 Barnes v. New Hampshire Karting Ass’n, Inc., 509 A.2d 151, 153 (1986) (exculpatory agreements) (“freedom of choice [means that] parties should be able to contract freely”); Essling v. Markman, 335 N.W.2d 237, 239 (Minn. 1983) (referring to “freedom of choice or contract”).

58 St. Francis Reg’l Med. Ctr., supra Footnote note 34, at 1464. (“Congress has chosen not to interfere with the parties’ own freedom of contract on this matter, so must we insist that the states not interfere with the parties’ freedom of choice.”)

59 See Ely, supra Footnote note 26.

60 See, e.g., 8 Richard A. Lord, Williston on Contracts § 18:8 (4th ed. May 2023).

61 Kugler v. Romain, 279 A.2d 640, 652 (N.J. 1971).

63 Arthur Young & Co. v. Vega III, 136 P.R. Dec. 157 (1994) (cited by PACIV, Inc. v. Perez Rivera, 159 P.R. Dec. 523, 2003 TSPR 84 (2003); TLS Mgmt. & Mktg. Servs., LLC v. Rodriguez-Toledo, 966 F.3d 46, 60 (1st Cir. 2020)).

64 McGrew v. Indus. Comm’n, 85 P.2d 608, 613 (Utah 1938).

65 Brief of Defendants/Appellees at 31, Gerhart, 852 F.3d 722 (No. 15-3292) (emphasis added).

66 Brief of the National Community Pharmacists Association at 3, Gerhart, 852 F.3d 722 (No. 15-3292).

67 Footnote Id. at 4.

68 Brief Amici Curiae of AARP et al., at 13–14, Gobeille, 577 U.S. 312 (No. 14-181).

69 Brief of Amici Curiae American Hospital Association, at 14, Gobeille, 577 U.S. 312 (No. 14-181).

70 Brief for the United States at 16, Gobeille, 577 U.S. 312 (No. 14-181); Brief for the States of New York et al. at 10–17, Gobeille, 577 U.S. 312 (No. 14-181) (hereinafter New York brief).

71 The closest was the US Department of Justice, which mentions it in passing. Brief for the United States at 19, Gobeille, 577 U.S. 312 (No. 14-181) (“over a dozen States have determined that such informational efforts can improve their citizens’ healthcare, lower costs, and enhance consumer choice”).

72 Brief of Amicus Curiae Connecticut Health Insurance Exchange at 2, Gobeille, 577 U.S. 312 (No. 14-181); Brief of Amici Curiae American Hospital Association, supra Footnote note 69.

73 Brief for Petitioner at 12, Gobeille, 577 U.S. 312 (No. 14-181).

74 Reply Brief for Petitioner at 23, Gobeille, 577 U.S. 312 (No. 14-181).

75 New York brief, supra Footnote note 70, at 18–19.

76 State All Payer Claims Databases Advisory Committee (SAPCDAC), U.S. Dep’t of Labor, https://www.dol.gov/agencies/ebsa/about-ebsa/about-us/state-all-payer-claims-databases-advisory-committee.

77 Michael K. Gusmano et al., Patient-Centered Care, Yes; Patients as Consumers, No, 38 Health Affs. 368, 370 (2019).

6 States as Contractor Attempts to Drive Health Care Cost Containment through State Purchasing Power

* Authors wish to thank Rachel Schwab and Kevin Lucia for their helpful edits and suggestions, as well as other faculty and staff at the Center on Health Insurance Reforms for their insights and inspiration.

1 See, e.g., David A. Super, Privatization, Policy Paralysis, and the Poor, 96 Calif. L. Rev. 393 (2008); Gillian E. Metzger, Privatization as Delegation, 103 Colum. L. Rev. 1367, 1376–400 (2003); Jody Freeman, The Contracting State, 28 Fla. St. U. L. Rev. 155, 176–88 (2000).

2 Jody Freeman, The Private Role in Public Governance, 75 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 543, 671 (2000).

3 Irene Papanicolas et al., Health Care Spending in the United States and Other High-Income Countries, 319 JAMA 1024, 1024 (2018).

4 Gerard F. Anderson et al., It’s Still the Prices, Stupid: Why the US Spends So Much on Health Care, and a Tribute to Uwe Reinhardt, 38 Health Affs. 87, 93 (2019).

5 Cong. Budget Off., Policy Approaches to Reduce What Commercial Insurers Pay for Hospitals’ and Physicians’ Services 1 (2022), https://www.cbo.gov/publication/58222.

6 Gary Claxton et al., Employer Health Benefits: 2023 Annual Survey, Kaiser Family Found. 90–91, 111–14, 132–34 (2023), https://files.kff.org/attachment/Employer-Health-Benefits-Survey-2023-Annual-Survey.pdf.

7 Inside Big Health Insurers’ Side Hustle, Tradeoffs (Sept. 23, 2021), https://tradeoffs.org/2021/09/23/inside-big-health-insurers-side-hustle/; Marshall Allen, Why Your Health Insurer Doesn’t Care about Your Big Bills, Nat’l Pub. Radio (May 25, 2018, 5:00 AM), https://www.npr.org/sections/health-shots/2018/05/25/613685732/why-your-health-insurer-doesnt-care-about-your-big-bills.

8 Erin C. Fuse Brown, Resurrecting Health Care Rate Regulation, 67 Hastings L.J. 85, 128–29 (2015).

9 Provider Rate Regulation, The Source on HealthCare Price and Competition (May 2023), https://sourceonhealthcare.org/provider-rate-regulation/; Linda J. Blumberg et al., Can Employer-Sponsored Insurance Be Saved? A Review of Policy Options: Price Regulation, CHIRblog (Jan. 18, 2023), https://chirblog.org/can-esi-be-saved-review-of-policy-options-price-regulation/.

10 Provider Rate Regulation, supra Footnote note 9; Len M. Nichols et al., Are Market Forces Strong Enough to Deliver Efficient Health Care Systems? Confidence Is Waning, 23(2) Health Affs. 8 (2004); Gail B. Agrawal & Howard R. Veit, Back to the Future: The Managed Care Revolution, 65(4) Law & Contemp. Probs. 11 (2002).

11 Fuse Brown, supra Footnote note 8, at 138.

12 Rachel Cohrs, The Health Care Issue Democrats Can’t Solve: Hospital Reform, STAT News (Oct. 26, 2023), https://www.statnews.com/2023/10/26/the-health-care-issue-democrats-cant-solve-hospital-reform.

13 See Allen, supra Footnote note 7; Katie Keith, Insurer Accountability in the Next Generation of Health Reform, 15 St. Louis U. J. Health L. & Pol’y 331, 339–40 (2022).

14 See, e.g., Joseph Antos & James C. Capretta, The Road Not Taken, in The Trillion Dollar Revolution 66, 71–72 (Ezekiel J. Emanuel & Abbe R. Gluck eds., 2020).

15 See generally Timothy Stoltzfus Jost & Katie Keith, ACA Litigation: Politics Pursued through Other Means, 45 J. Health Pol., Pol’y, & Law 485 (2020).

16 Sabrina Corlette & JoAnn Volk, Active Purchasing for Health Insurance Exchange: An Analysis of Options, Nat’l Acad. Soc. Ins. 4 (June 2011), https://www.nasi.org/wp-content/uploads/2011/06/Active_Purchasing_for_Health_Insurance_Exchanges.pdf (quoting Alain C. Enthoven, The History and Principles of Managed Competition, 12 Health Affs. 24, 29 (Supp. 1993)).

17 Footnote Id. at 7.

18 Sabrina Corlette et al., The Massachusetts and Utah Health Exchanges: Lessons Learned, Georgetown Univ. Health Pol’y Inst. Ctr. for Children and Families (Mar. 2011), https://ccf.georgetown.edu/wp-content/uploads/2012/03/Health-reform_exchanges.pdf.

20 James C. Robinson et al., Whither Health Insurance Exchanges under the Affordable Care Act? Active Purchasing versus Passive Marketplaces, Health Affs. Forefront (Oct. 2, 2015), https://www.healthaffairs.org/content/forefront/whither-health-insurance-exchanges-under-affordable-care-act-active-purchasing-versus.

22 Al Bingham et al., National vs. California Comparison: Detailed Data Help Explain the Risk Differences Which Drive Covered California’s Success, Health Affs. Forefront (July 11, 2018), https://www.healthaffairs.org/do/10.1377/forefront.20180710.459445/full/.

23 Colo. Rev. Stat. § 10-22-104.

24 See, e.g., William Kramer, Why Aren’t State Exchanges Embracing Prudent Purchasing Strategies?, Health Affs. Forefront (Mar. 19, 2012), https://www.healthaffairs.org/content/forefront/why-aren-t-state-exchanges-embracing-prudent-purchasing-strategies. This rationale, however, does not apply to states funding subsidies that supplement federal financial assistance.

25 Robinson et al., supra Footnote note 20.

26 See Jaime S. King et al., Are State Public Option Health Plans Worth It, 59 Harv. J. on Legis. 145, 150–51, 166–68, 174–77 (Winter 2022); Christine Monahan et al., State Public Option-Style Laws: What Policymakers Need to Know, Commonwealth Fund (July 23, 2021), https://www.commonwealthfund.org/blog/2021/state-public-option-style-laws-what-policymakers-need-know. Colorado also has implemented a quasi-public option law, but it legally requires all insurers to offer “Colorado Option plans” that meet statutory premium reduction targets, and, if these targets are not met, authorizes the state to administratively order health care providers to participate in Colorado Option plan networks at state-imposed reimbursement rates. See Monahan et al.

27 Off. of Fin. Mgmt. (Wash. State), Multiple Agency Fiscal Note Summary: 5377SB, 3 (2021), https://fnspublic.ofm.wa.gov/FNSPublicSearch/GetPDF?packageID=62340. An earlier version of the bill amending Washington’s public option law would have required certain hospitals systems to contract with at least one MBPO. See S. Rep. SB 5377, at 5–6 (Wash. Feb. 22, 2021), https://lawfilesext.leg.wa.gov/biennium/2021–22/Pdf/Bill%20Reports/Senate/5377%20SBR%20WM%20OC%2021.pdf?q=20211031060456.

28 Julie Appleby, “Holy Cow” Moment Changes How Montana’s State Health Plan Does Business, Kaiser Health News (June 20, 2018), https://khn.org/news/holy-cow-moment-changes-how-montanas-state-health-plan-does-business/.

29 Adney Rakotoniaina, Overview of States’ Hospital Reference-Based Pricing to Medicare Initiative, Nat’l Acad. for State Health Pol’y (Oct. 19, 2021), https://nashp.org/overview-of-states-hospital-reference-based-pricing-to-medicare-initiatives/.

30 Sabrina Corlette et al., Unleashing the Giant: Opportunities for State Employee Health Plans to Drive Improvements in Affordability, Ctr. on Health Ins. Reforms 22 (June 2021), https://sehpcostcontainment.chir.georgetown.edu/documents/SEHP-report-final.pdf.

31 Footnote Id. at 23.

32 See, e.g., Adney Rakotoniaina, How Oregon Is Limiting Hospital Payments and Cost Growth for State Employee Health Plans, Nat’l Acad. for State Health Pol’y (Aug. 30, 2021), https://nashp.org/how-oregon-is-limiting-hospital-payments-and-cost-growth-for-state-employee-health-plans/.

33 Corlette et al., supra Footnote note 30, at 23.

34 Footnote Id. at 15.

35 Theresa Opeka, Appeals from BCBSNC & UMR, Inc. Rejected by NC State Health Plan, Carolina J. (Jan. 20, 2023), https://www.carolinajournal.com/appeals-from-bcbsnc-umr-inc-rejected-by-nc-state-health-plan/.

36 C. J. Staff, Blue Cross NC Takes State Health Plan Decision to Court, Carolina J. (Feb. 16, 2023), https://www.carolinajournal.com/blue-cross-nc-takes-state-health-plan-decision-to-court/.

37 See Brian C. Blase, Demonstrate Leadership: Reform the State Employee Health Plan, in Don’t Wait for Washington: How States Can Reform Health Care Today 9–20 (Brian C. Blase ed., 2021).

38 Martha Minow, Public and Private Partnerships: Accounting for the New Religion, 116 Harv. L. Rev. 1229, 1230 (2003).

7 Adaptation of Tort Law to Modern Health Care Delivery in the Restatement of Medical Malpractice

* I serve as a Reporter for this Restatement project along with Nora Freeman Engstrom and Michael D. Green.

1 Countless discussions of these themes can be found, but each owes its intellectual debt to the classic work of Oliver Wendell Holmes Jr., The Common Law (1881).

2 My co-reporters, for instance, canvass a number of such examples in their review of a companion Restatement project called Torts: Miscellaneous Provisions. See Nora F. Engstrom & Michael D. Green, Tort Theory and Restatements: Of Immanence and Lizard Lips, 14 J. Tort Law 333 (2021).

3 John C. P. Goldberg, Torts in the American Law Institute, in The American Law Institute: A Centennial History (Andrew S. Gold & Robert W. Gordon eds., 2023).

4 Restatement (Second) of Torts § 299A (Am. Law Inst. 1969).

5 For historical accounts, see, e.g., Kenneth A. DeVille, Medical Malpractice in Nineteenth-Century America (1990); Iain Hay, Money, Medicine, and Malpractice in American Society (1992); James C. Mohr, American Medical Malpractice Litigation in Historical Perspective, 283 JAMA 1731 (2000).

6 Mark Hall, The History and Future of Health Care Law: An Essentialist View, 41 Wake Forest L. Rev. 347 (2006).

7 This analysis is based on the current version of the project’s drafting, which is not yet completed.

8 As with other Restatements, this one addresses only the common law, and not statutory law. Many states, however, have statutes that codify medical liability essentials. In doing so, statutory law embraces common law concepts and thus decisions interpreting and applying these statutes often employ common law reasoning.

9 § 2 cmt. k. Unless otherwise noted, section numbers refer to the current version of the Restatement (Third) of Torts: Medical Malpractice.

10 § 2 cmt. n. As an example, the Reporters’ Note mentions the classic decision in Hurley v. Eddingfield, 59 N.E. 1058, 1058 (Ind. 1901), which absolved a general practitioner from refusing to aid a former patient who ended up dying during childbirth. Although the court noted that the doctor “had been decedent’s family physician,” the court (without discussion) treated this as a refusal to initiate, rather than to continue, a treatment relationship.

11 § 2 cmt. n.

12 See Goldberg, supra Footnote note 3 for additional discussion.

13 § 12 cmt. k.

14 In addition to the examples discussed in text, also relevant is the long-standing doctrine that, in applying res ipsa loquitor to mishaps in surgical settings, courts rule that it is sufficient if anyone on the surgical team was probably at fault, rather than requiring the plaintiff to identify which particular actor was most likely responsible. § 7 cmt. b. In essence, this variation in the doctrine holds the entire team responsible for any member’s mistake, unless evidence emerges about which particular team member was at fault.

15 See Stephen H. Price, The Sinking of the “Captain of the Ship”: Reexamining the Vicarious Liability of an Operating Surgeon for the Negligence of Assisting Hospital Personnel, 10 J. Leg. Med. 323 (1989).

16 See §15 reporters’ note cmt. e.

17 § 15 cmt. g.

18 As summarized by Restatement (Third) of Agency § 7.03 cmt. d(2) (Am. Law Inst. 2006), owing to the highly fact-intensive nature of the inquiry, “[e]ven within the same jurisdiction, it may be difficult to predict whether a given set of indicia will demonstrate that a special employer has assumed the right of control.” The associated Reporter’s Note points in particular to “examples drawn from medical-malpractice cases [to] illustrate the fact-specificity of borrowed-servant cases [and hence their unpredictable outcomes], regardless of the doctrinal formulation a court applies.”

19 Holger v. Irish, 851 P.2d 1122, 1127–28 (Or. 1993).

20 § 15 reporters’ note cmt. e.

21 As another example, under-informed consent law courts hold the principal physician solely responsible for making necessary disclosures even though physicians, following institutional policies, often delegate such tasks to subordinates employed and supervised by hospitals. § 15, cmt. e. See also note infra.

22 Similarly, the § 1 Reporters’ Note to comment g observes that the Restatement only partially and thus inadequately accounts for the fact that “many bad outcomes result from poor system design or multiple reinforcing mistakes rather than primarily from individual error” and that, accordingly, “it is widely accepted that a systems approach is needed to improve medical quality and reduce medical error.”

23 Various examples the Restatement gives and documents include medical examinations for purposes of employer or insurance, physicians who supervise nurse practitioners or physician assistants, consulting and on-call arrangements. See also Mark A. Hall et al., Liability Implications of Physician-Directed Care Coordination, 3 Ann. Fam. Med. 115, 115–20 (2005) (discussing the limited legal exposure of physicians who coordinate care in managed care settings).

24 Possibly, this reluctance to push harder is informed by a concern that doing so may deter professionals from assuming new responsibilities that, if they were not professionally controllable, would carry unknown liability risks.

25 Am. Law Inst., Reporters’ Study on Enterprise Responsibility for Personal Injury (1991).

26 Recounting this history, see Engstrom & Green, supra Footnote note 2, at 341; Goldberg, supra Footnote note 3, at nn. 104–17.

27 Indeed, that term purposefully does not appear in the official Comments, but only in the § 15 Reporters’ Note to comment f. For further discussion of potential enterprise liability for hospitals or managed care insurers, see generally Kenneth Abraham & Paul Weiler, Enterprise Liability and the Evolution of the American Health Care System, 108 Harv. L. Rev. 381 (1994); Kenneth Abraham & Paul Weiler, Enterprise Medical Liability and the Choice of the Responsible Enterprise, 20 Am. J.L. & Med. 29 (1994); Clark C. Havighurst, Making Health Plans Accountable for the Quality of Care, 31 Ga. L. Rev. 587 (1997); Philip G. Peters, Resuscitating Hospital Enterprise Liability, 73 Mo. L. Rev. 369, 369–97 (2008); William Sage, Enterprise Liability and the Emerging Managed Care Health Care System, 60 Law & Contemp. Probs. 159 (Spring 1997).

28 § 14 cmt. a.

29 § 13(a), (c).

30 See, e.g., §13 cmts. a, i, & j.

31 § 15(2) & cmt. i.

32 § 15 cmt. a.

33 Footnote Id. cmt. c.

34 Restatement (Third) of Agency § 7.03, supra Footnote note 18.

35 § 15 cmt. i.

37 Indeed, it endorses one particularly retrograde position that, based on substantial case law, absolves hospitals from responsibility for ensuring that patients’ informed consent is obtained for physician treatment – despite the fact that hospitals routinely take measures to ensure that physicians comply with their informed consent obligations. § 12 reporters’ note cmt. e. The reason courts give for abnormally limiting institutional responsibility is in order to keep the central focus of responsibility for informed consent on the treating physician. Although scholars find this reason unconvincing, case law currently is too consistent for the Restatement to reject it outright. See Footnote id.

38 § 15 cmt. i.

8 Pandemic Harms and Private Law’s Limits A Proposal for Tort Replacement

1 Justine Coleman, Cruz Predicts “Tidal Wave” of Lawsuits against Reopening Small Businesses without Legislation, The Hill (May 6, 2020), https://thehill.com/homenews/senate/496351-cruz-predicts-tidal-wave-of-lawsuits-against-reopening-small-businesses.

2 See Elaine S. Povich, States Braced for a Wave of COVID-19 Lawsuits. It Never Arrived, Stateline.org (July 21, 2021), https://perma.cc/BX29-FXW7/.

3 See generally 50-State Update on COVID-19 Business Liability Protections, Husch Blackwell (Feb. 22, 2021; updated Mar. 18, 2021), https://perma.cc/A6LV-W4C2.

4 Number of COVID-19 deaths reported to WHO (cumulative total), United States of America, World Health Org., https://perma.cc/M767-DQVF (last accessed Sept. 25, 2024); Effects of COVID-19 Pandemic on Workplace Injuries and Illnesses, Compensation, Occupational Requirements, and Work Stoppages Statistics, U.S. Bureau of Lab. Stat., https://perma.cc/AVH4-BFAL (last accessed Sept. 25, 2024).

5 COVID-19’s Total Cost to the U.S. Economy Will Reach $14 Trillion by End of 2023, USC Schaeffer (May 16, 2023), https://perma.cc/93EQ-ACAB.

6 Qihao He et al., The Possibilities and Limits of Insurance as Governance in Insuring Pandemics, Nat’l Libr. of Med. (2023), https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC10028328/; Steven Ross Johnson, Millions at High Risk of Severe COVID-19 Outcomes Lack Coverage to Cover Costs, Modern Healthcare (June 10, 2020), https://perma.cc/38AT-LDFK.

7 Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., The Common Law 49 (1881).

8 Federal Coal Mine Health and Safety Act, Pub. L. No. 91-173, 83 Stat. 798 (codified as amended at 30 U.S.C. § 901 et seq.).

9 30 U.S.C. § 901(a).

10 Robert L. Rabin, The Renaissance of Accident Law Plans Revisited, 64 Md. L. Rev. 699, 704 (2005).

11 Peter S. Barth, The Tragedy of Black Lung: Federal Compensation for Occupational Disease 169–71 (1987).

12 30 U.S.C. § 921.

14 Exec. Order No. 13179, Providing Compensation to America’s Nuclear Weapons Workers (Dec. 7, 2000).

16 42 U.S.C. § 7384 et seq.

17 The Act/EEOICPA, Part B, Ctrs. for Disease Control and Prevention, https://perma.cc/3Y2B-E45W.

18 49 U.S.C. § 40101. See also Raymond L. Mariani, The September 11th Victim Compensation Fund of 2001 and the Protection of the Airline Industry: A Bill for the American People, 67 J. Air L. & Com. 141, 142 (2002).

19 Preamble Public Law No: 107-42 (Sept. 22, 2001).

20 49 U.S.C. § 40101, sec. 101(a)(2).

21 Footnote Id. at sec. 101(a)(1).

22 Footnote Id. at sec. 405(c)(3)(B)(i).

23 Footnote Id. at sec. 408.

24 Footnote Id. at sec. 201(b)(2).

25 Kenneth S. Abraham & K. D. Logue, The Genie and the Bottle: Collateral Sources and the 9/11 Victim Compensation Fund, 53 DePaul L. Rev. 591, 595 (2003).

26 See, e.g., Troyen A. Brennan et al., Incidence of Adverse Events and Negligence in Hospitalized Patients – Results of the Harvard Medical Practice Study I, 324 N. Engl. J. Med. 370 (1991); Lucian Leape et al., The Nature of Adverse Events in Hospitalized Patients: Results of the Harvard Medical Malpractice Study II, 324 N. Engl. J. Med 377 (1991); David M. Studdert et al., Claims, Errors, and Compensation Payments in Medical Malpractice Litigation, 354 N. Engl. J. Med. 2024 (2006); Allen B. Kachalia et al., Beyond Negligence: Availability and Medical Injury Compensation, 66 Soc. Sci. Med. 387 (2008); Eric J. Thomas et al., Incidence and Types of Preventable Adverse Events in Elderly Patients: Population Based Review of Medical Records, 38 Med. Care. 261 (2000).

27 Catherine Struve, Improving the Medical Malpractice Litigation Process, 23(4) Health Affs. 33, 34 (2004).

28 See, e.g., David M. Studdert & Troyen A. Brennan, No-Fault Compensation for Medical Injuries: The Prospect for Error Prevention, 286(2) JAMA 217–23 (2001); Marie Bismark & Ron Patterson, No-Fault Compensation in New Zealand: Harmonizing Injury Compensation, Provider Accountability, and Patient Safety, 25(1) Health Affs. 278, 278–83 (2006); Randall R. Bovbjerg & Frank Sloan, No Fault for Medical Injury: Theory and Evidence, 67 U. Cincinnati L. Rev. 53 (1998).

29 Don Berwick, A User’s Manual for the IOM’s “Quality Chasm” Report, 21(3) Health Affs. 89 (2002).

30 James A. Henderson, The Virginia Birth-Related Injury Compensation Act: Limited No-Fault Statutes as Solutions to the “Medical Malpractice Crisis,” in Medical Professional Liability and Delivery of Obstetrical Care: Volume II: An Interdisciplinary Review 194 (Victoria P. Rostow & Roger J. Bulger eds., 1989).

31 Jill Horwitz & Troyen A. Brennan, No-Fault Compensation for Medical Injury: A Case Study, 14(4) Health Affs. 164 (1995).

32 Footnote Id. See also Cynthia L. Gallup, Can No-Fault Compensation of Impaired Infants Alleviate the Malpractice Crisis in Obstetrics?, 14(4) J. Health Pol. Pol’y L. 691 (1989), https://read.dukeupress.edu/jhppl/article/14/4/691/74327/Can-No-Fault-Compensation-of-Impaired-Infants.

33 Gil Siegal et al., Adjudicating Severe Birth Injury Claims in Florida and Virginia: The Experience of a Landmark Experiment in Personal Injury Compensation, 34 Am. J.L. & Med. 489 (2008).

34 Richard A. Epstein, The Historical Origins and Economic Structure of Workers’ Compensation Law, 16 Ga. L. Rev. 775, 777–78 (1982).

36 Gregory P. Guyton, A Brief History of Workers’ Compensation, 19 Iowa Orthopaedic J. 106 (1999), https://perma.cc/M7CU-EGRE.

37 Footnote Id. at 107.

38 Footnote Id. at 108.

39 Horwitz thanks Professor Don Herzog for this insight.

40 Innovative financing would be necessary to support what would be an expensive program. Because protecting businesses, especially small businesses, from ruinous lawsuits partly motivates the proposal, legislatures might contemplate a special tax on businesses to generate a fund. Although such a tax might become complex in implementation (e.g., are lawyers involved? Are punitive damages available?), not to mention politically difficult, the issues are not insurmountable, as the creation of enduring or sinking funds is a budget device familiar to Congress and state legislatures.

9 The Human Body Commons A Private Law Contribution for the Advancement of the Right to Health

1 See Sheldon Krimsky, The Profit of Scientific Discovery and Its Normative Implications, 75(1) Chi.-Kent L. Rev. 15, 17 (1999). (“(I)n the mid-1950s, the federal government provided about fifty-five percent of the support for university research, industrial firm supplied eight percent of the funds and the remaining thirty-seven percent came from foundations and state governments. By the late 1960’s, the government share expanded to more than seventy rising budget deficits and the leveling of science funding in the 1980s.”)

2 Jerome H. Reichman & Paul F. Uhlir, A Contractually Reconstructed Research Commons for Scientific Data in a Highly Protectionist Intellectual Property Environment, 66 L. & Contemp. Probs. 315 (2003).

3 James Boyle, The Public Domain: Enclosing the Commons of the Mind (2008).

4 Krimsky, supra Footnote note 1.

5 Tine de Moor, What Do We Have in Common? A Comparative Framework for Old and New Literature on the Commons 57(2) Int’l Rev. Soc. Hist. 269, 272 (2012).

6 See, e.g., Carol Rose, The Comedy of the Commons: Custom, Commerce, and Inherently Public Property, 53(3) Univ. Chi. L. Rev. 711 (1986), https://www.jstor.org/stable/1599583?seq=1&cid=pdf-; James Boyle, The Public Domain: Enclosing the Commons of the Mind (2008); Yochai Benkler, The Wealth of Networks: How Social Production Transforms Markets and Freedom (2006); Yochai Benkler, Between Spanish Huertas and the Open Road, in Governing Knowledge Commons 69–98 (Brett Frischmann et al. eds., 2014); Yochai Benkler, The Political Economy of Commons, IV(3) Upgrade Eur. J. Informatics Pro. 6, 6–9 (2003); Yochai Benkler, Open Access and Information Commons, in 2 The Oxford Handbook of Law and Economics: Private and Commercial Law 256, 256 (Francesco Parisi ed., 2017); Lawrence Lessig, Code and the Commons, Keynote Address at Fordham L. Sch. Conference on Media Convergence (Feb. 9, 1999), https://dash.harvard.edu/bitstream/handle/1/12942294/COMMONS?sequence=1; Brett M. Frischmann, Infrastructure: The Social Value of Shared Resources (2012).

7 Elinor Ostrom, Governing the Commons: The Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action (1990); Elinor Ostrom, Background on the Institutional Analysis and Development Framework, 39(1) Pol’y Stud. J. 7 (2011).

8 Tine de Moor, From Common Pastures to Global Commons: A Historical Perspective on Interdisciplinary Approaches to Commons, 19(4) Natures Sci. Societes 422, 422–31 (2011); De Moor, supra Footnote note 5.

9 Even if one may formally find different underlying titles of property, it is the case of some types of infrastructure falling under the public property regime.

10 Charlotte Hess & Elinor Ostrom, Understanding Knowledge as a Commons: From Theory to Practice 5 (2007); De Moor, supra Footnote note 5, at 426.

11 David Bollier, The Growth of the Commons Paradigm, in Hess & Ostrom, supra Footnote note 10, at 27.

12 The European Data Protection Regulation (GDPR), for example, prohibits as a rule the processing data without the consent of the data subject. However, the GDPR also established a series of exceptions, among which the use of sensitive data for scientific research. See Enrique Santamaría, Governing Health Data for Research, Development and Innovation: The Missteps of the European Health Data Space Proposal, Bill of Health (Mar. 23, 2023), https://blog.petrieflom.law.harvard.edu/2023/03/23/governing-health-data-for-research-development-and-innovation-the-missteps-of-the-european-health-data-space-proposal/ (with further references).

13 Bollier, supra Footnote note 11, at 34.

14 Governing Medical Knowledge Commons (Katherine J. Strandburg et al. eds., 2017).

15 Jorge L. Contreas & Bartha M. Knoppers, The Genomic Commons, 19 Ann. Rev. Genomics Hum. Genetics 429 (2018); Jorge L. Contreras, Constructing the Genome Commons, 99 Governing Knowledge Commons 112, 112–13 (Brett M. Frichmann et al. eds., 2014). Similar proposals for commons on the results on genetic tests have also been advanced, see, e.g., Barbara J. Evans, Genomic Data Commons, in Governing Medical Knowledge Commons 74, 74–101 (Katherine J. Strandburg et al. eds., 2017).

16 Robert Cook-Deegan & Amy L. McGuire, Moving beyond Bermuda: Sharing Data to Build a Medical Information Commons, 27(6) Genome Rsch. 897 (2017); Robert Cook-Deegan et al., Sharing Data to Build a Medical Information Commons: From Bermuda to the Global Alliance, 18 Ann. Rev. Genomics Hum. Genetics 389, 389–415 (2017); Patricia A. Deverka et al., Creating a Data Resource: What Will It Take to Build a Medical Information Commons?, 9(1) Genome Med. 1 (2017).

17 The point of departure of these theories is either: (1) Hess and Ostrom’s variation of IAD framework for data and information which – together with other intelligible ideas and scientific knowledge – are covered under the umbrella term “knowledge commons,” and/or (2) the Governing Knowledge Commons framework (GKC) developed by Katherine J. Strandburg, Brett M. Frischmann, and Michael J. Madison. See, e.g., Hess & Ostrom, supra Footnote note 10, at 7; Governing Knowledge Commons (Brett M. Frischmann et al. eds., 2014).

18 See Reichman & Uhlir, supra Footnote note 2 (providing information on contractual models for scientific data commons); Arti Rai & James Boyle, Synthetic Biology: Caught between Property Rights, the Public Domain, and the Commons, 5(3) PLOS Biology 389 (2007) (providing a specific analysis in the field of synthetic biology).

19 See Victor Rodriguez, Material Transfer Agreements: Open Science vs. Proprietary Claims, 23(4) Nature Biotech. 489, 489–91 (2005) (an overview of the notion of material transfer agreement and the debate around open science on human materials).

20 Int’l Soc’y for Biological and Env’t Repositories (ISBER), Best Practices for Repositories: Collection, Storage, Retrieval and Distribution of Biological Materials for Research 88 (3rd ed. 2001).

21 Lisa Dive et al., Public Trust and Global Biobank Networks, 21 BMC Med. Ethics 1 (2020).

22 Uniform Biological Material Transfer Agreement, dated March 8, 1995, for the Transfer of Materials between Non-Profit Institutions and an Implementing Letter for the Transfer of Biological Material, World Intell. Prop. Org. (1995) https://www.wipo.int/tk/en/databases/contracts/texts/ubmta.html.

23 Thinh Kguyen, Science Commons: Material Transfer Agreement Project, 3(2) Innovations Tech., Governance, Globalization 137, 137–43 (2007).

24 Linda Kahl et al., Opening Options for Material Transfer, 36(10) Nature Biotech. 923, 923–27 (2018).

25 Kguyen, supra Footnote note 23, at 140.

26 More than 300 institutions have become signatories of the UBMTA. See UMBTA Signatories, Ass’n of Univ. Tech. Managers, https://autm.net/surveys-and-tools/agreements/material-transfer-agreements/mta-toolkit/uniform-biological-material-transfer-agreement/ubmta-signatories (last accessed May 8, 2023). Addgene, one of the biggest repositories of plasmids in the world, is an example of successful implementation of the UBMTA. Addgene, acting as an intermediary, continues to use the UBMTA for sharing plasmids deposited in its repository. See MTA: UBMTA, Addgene, https://www.addgene.org/agreement/1/ (last accessed May 8, 2023).

27 The Open MTA was developed as a collaborative effort led by the Biobricks Foundation and the OpenPlant Synthetic Biology Research Centre. See Frequently Asked Questions, BioBricks Found., https://biobricks.org/openmta-faq/ (last accessed May 8, 2023); The Open Material Transfer Agreement, BioBricks Found., https://biobricks.org/open-material-transfer-agreement/ (last accessed May 8, 2023).

28 Darren Shickle et al., Inter- and Intra-biobank Networks: Classification of Biobanks, 77(4) Pathobiology 181, 181–90 (2010).

29 See Andrea Boggio, Population Biobanks’ Governance: A Case Study of Knowledge Commons, in Governing Medical Knowledge Commons 102–20 (2017) (a parallel between population biobanks and knowledge commons).

30 Niva Elkin-Koren, What Contracts Cannot Do: The Limits of Private Ordering in Facilitating a Creative Commons, 74 Fordham L. Rev. 375 (2005).

31 For information on the Structural Genomics Consortium and the Open Science Trust Agreement, see Frequently Asked Questions – SGC Open Science Trust Agreement, Structural Genomics Consortium, https://www.thesgc.org/sgc-open-science-trust-agreements (last accessed May 8, 2023).

34 Aled Edwards et al., A Trust Approach for Sharing Research Reagents, 9(392) Sci. Translational Med. 1, 1–3 (2017). The idea of putting highly commercially valuable reagents and data in the public domain is not new. See, e.g., Declan Butler, GlaxoSmithKline Goes Public with Malaria Data, Nature (Jan. 20, 2010), https://www.nature.com/articles/news.2010.20 (Glaxo’s released 13,500 structures of possible drugs against Malaria into the public domain).

35 Here, the question on the existence of property rights on HBM is of paramount importance. However, it is beyond the scope of this chapter to dwell in this litigious issue.

36 See generally E. Hafen et al., Health Data Cooperatives – Citizen Empowerment, 53(2) Methods Info. Med. 82 (2014); Alessandro Blasimme et al., Democratizing Health Research through Data Cooperatives, 31(3) Phil. Tech. 473, 473–79 (2018); Van Ilse Roessel et al., Potentials and Challenges of the Health Data Cooperative Model, 20(6) Pub. Health Genomics 321 (2018).

37 Articles of Association, MIDATA Genossenschaft (2019), https://www.midata.coop/wp-content/uploads/2019/08/MIDATA_Statuten_20190626_EN.pdf.

38 Footnote Id. at 2 (Article 2(h)).

39 For a detailed analysis of privacy and MIDATA, see Felix Gille and Effy Vayena, How Private Individuals Maintain Privacy and Govern Their Own Health Data Cooperative: MIDATA in Switzerland, in Governing Privacy in Knowledge Commons 53–69 (Madelyn R. Sanfilippo et al. eds., 2021). On privacy in the commons, see generally Madelyn R. Sanfilippo et al., Governing Privacy in Knowledge Commons (2021).

40 Roberto Andorno, Human Dignity and Human Rights as a Common Ground for a Global Bioethics, 34(3) J. Med. Phil. 223 (2009); Roberto Andorno, Principles of International Biolaw: Seeking Common Ground at the Intersection of Bioethics and Human Rights (2013); Eric M. Meslin & Ibrahim Garba, Biobanking and Public Health: Is a Human Rights Approach the Tie that Binds?, 130(3) Hum. Genetics 451 (2011); Bartha M. Knoppers et al., A Human Rights Approach to an International Code of Conduct for Genomic and Clinical Data Sharing, 133(7) Hum. Genetics, 895 (2014).

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×