Hostname: page-component-7b9c58cd5d-hpxsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-03-15T05:54:02.906Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Property, redistribution, and the status quo: a laboratory study

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2025

Konstantin Chatziathanasiou*
Affiliation:
University of Münster, Münster, Germany
Svenja Hippel*
Affiliation:
University of Würzburg, Würzburg, Germany
Michael Kurschilgen*
Affiliation:
Technical University of Munich, Arcisstr. 21, 80333 Munich, Germany Max Planck Institute for Research on Collective Goods, Bonn, Germany
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We report experimental evidence showing a positive effect of redistribution on economic efficiency via the self-enforcement of property rights, and identify which status groups benefit more and which less. We model an economy in which wealth is produced if players voluntarily comply with the—efficient but inequitable—prevailing social order. We vary exogenously whether redistribution is feasible, and how it is organized. We find that redistribution benefits all status groups as property disputes recede. It is most effective when transfers are not discretionary but instead imposed by some exogenous administration. In the absence of coercive means to enforce property rights, it is the higher status groups, not the lower status groups, who benefit from redistribution being compulsory rather than voluntary.

Type
Original Paper
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC-BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s) 2020

1 Introduction

How does redistribution affect a person’s economic status? Conceiving redistribution simply as a means to channel wealth from the relatively rich to the relatively poor, the answer is pretty straightforward: it helps the poor, and hurts the rich. Yet the truth is likely to be more complex. A large strand of research in public and monetary economics describes negative behavioral responses to redistribution like lower labor supply, lower effort, and higher expenditures for tax professionals (for an overview of the vast theoretical and empirical literature, see Trabandt and Uhlig (Reference Trabandt and Uhlig2011), Saez et al. (Reference Saez, Slemrod and Giertz2012), and Doerrenberg et al. (Reference Doerrenberg, Peichl and Siegloch2017)). If the dead-weight loss is large, redistribution could potentially hurt both the rich and the poor. On the other hand, redistribution might also have a positive effect on economic efficiency by reducing conflict over property rights (Grossman Reference Grossman1994, Reference Grossman1995; Bös and Kolmar Reference Bös and Kolmar2003; Dal Bó and Dal Bó Reference Dal Bó and Dal Bó2011). But to this day there is no causal empirical evidence for such an effect. The present paper aims to fill that gap. Using a novel experimental paradigm, we test how redistribution affects efficiency via the self-enforcement of property rights, and identify which status groups benefit more and which less.Footnote 1

More effective self-enforcement could free up resources otherwise tied to enforcing property rights by coercive means, for more productive use. Expenditures for deterrence and coercion (police, judiciary, prisons, fences and walls, private security, etc.) are inherently unproductive, and thus socially wasteful (Skaperdas Reference Skaperdas1992; Hirshleifer Reference Hirshleifer1995). In fact, even in countries with expansive (and expensive) enforcement institutions, property rights are not perfectly secure.Footnote 2 The US Department of Justice, for instance, reports for 2018 a property crime rate of 108 victimizations per 1000 households.Footnote 3

Extracting causal evidence from historical or contemporary field data on this important question is extraordinarily difficult. Both redistribution, property rights, and law enforcement are endogenously determined through the political process. In today’s market democracies, a person’s economic status results from a mix of exogenous factors like inheritance and descent (Bowles and Gintis Reference Bowles and Gintis2002; Kahlenberg Reference Kahlenberg2010; Chetty et al. Reference Chetty, Hendren, Kline and Saez2014; Adermon et al. Reference Adermon, Lindahl and Waldenström2018) and endogenous factors like effort and acquired skill. Moreover, economic status may come along with the power to coerce others and to bend the rules of society to one’s advantage (Glaeser et al. Reference Glaeser, Scheinkman and Shleifer2003; Acemoglu et al. Reference Acemoglu, Naidu, Restrepo and Robinson2015). To generate causal evidence, we therefore design a laboratory environment with (a) no coercive enforcement of property rights, (b) exogenous variation of redistribution, and (c) an exogenous status measure that is orthogonal to other individual characteristics like preferences, productivity, and coercive power.

In particular, we model an N-players society of strangers whose members regularly experience anonymous bilateral encounters with one another. Wealth is produced by avoiding disputes over property rights, for which players need to voluntarily agree on who claims property of a coveted resource, and who concedes. The resulting stage game is a Battle-of-the-Sexes (BoS). An individual’s status in society is determined by the status quo, reflecting some prevailing legal or social order: a pre-birth lottery ranks players from highest to lowest degree of privilege. Whenever two players meet, they mutually and unambiguously recognize who is of higher status (and thus supposed to claim the resource) and who is of lower status (and thus supposed to concede that right to the other player). The higher (lower) one’s rank, the more often the action recommended by the status quo is to claim (concede).

We illustrate that, with standard preferences, the status quo functions as a correlation device (Aumann Reference Aumann1974, Reference Aumann1987), and enables frictionless, efficient coordination of otherwise conflicting claims. The correlated equilibrium has a bourgeois character (Bhaskar Reference Bhaskar2000; Gintis Reference Gintis2007), as players comply with the prevailing order and concede to whoever is higher on the ladder. Thus—in equilibrium—the pre-birth status order becomes a self-enforced convention for allocating individual property rights between all members of society; a person’s pre-birth status determines her economic status.Footnote 4 But in the presence of behavioral types (Embrey et al. Reference Embrey, Frechette and Lehrer2015) who deviate from the prescribed order, the convention is fragile. The lower a player’s rank, the lower her incentives to stick to the order. Theoretically, redistribution stabilizes the bourgeois equilibrium by increasing players’ tolerance against occasional deviators.Footnote 5

In a series of experimental treatments, we vary whether redistributive transfers are feasible or not, and compare the effectiveness of different ways to organize redistribution, reflecting stylized transfer institutions with varying degrees of centralization: societies that rely predominantly on alms, tipping, and charity, versus societies with highly centralized welfare states. Specifically, we focus on two dimensions of centralization: (a) whether transfers are paid directly to the beneficiary or indirectly, via a central redistribution pool, and (b) whether players have full discretion over the amount they transfer or transfers of the very same amount are exogenously imposed by some central administration. The comparison between a direct vs. a pooled transfer institution indicates how agents’ willingness to provide transfers reacts to diffusion of responsibility (Dana et al. Reference Dana, Weber and Kuang2007; Hamman et al. Reference Hamman, Loewenstein and Weber2010; Bartling et al. Reference Bartling, Weber and Yao2014). Comparing discretionary vs. exogenously imposed transfers yields insights into the mechanism through which transfers affect a player’s willingness to concede. As we hold average transfer levels and thus payoff asymmetry constant by design, differences in effectiveness cannot stem from distributional concerns. Instead, they would suggest a different perception of transfers coming from an impersonal process rather than from another human being.

We find that (1) in the absence of redistribution institutions, the status quo translates into an inefficient, pronounced payoff hierarchy. The Gini coefficient is .30 and efficiency reaches only 47% of its potential as players’ willingness to concede decreases with their rank on the status ladder. (2) Voluntary redistribution (both direct and indirect) makes all ranks better off as property disputes recede. The Gini coefficient drops to .18 and efficiency increases to 67%. Groups with higher willingness to transfer and thus lower payoff asymmetry systematically achieve higher levels of efficiency. (3) Whereas the effectiveness of voluntary transfers stagnates around 70%, property disputes continue to recede over time when transfers are exogenously imposed, reaching 85% efficiency in late rounds. (4) Virtually all the added surplus of the exogenously imposed redistribution accrues to the upper half of the pre-birth status ladder. (5) By keeping the transfer volume constant, we identify an additional obstacle to the self-enforcement of property rights, besides payoff asymmetry. Exogenously administered, compulsory redistribution is more effective at persuading lower ranks to obey the rules of the status quo by mitigating the dissatisfaction from receiving disappointing transfers.

In sum, our paper documents the existence of a Pareto-improving effect of redistribution via the self-enforcement of property rights. We thus corroborate the conjectures of a strand of theoretical contributions in political economy. Grossman (Reference Grossman1994), for instance, models a society of landowners, who earn rents from their land holdings, and peasants, who choose between allocating time to wage employment (on the landlord’s premises), self-employment (on their own land), and banditry. He shows that when the technology of banditry is sufficiently effective, redistribution by means of a land reform is the landowners’ optimal response to the threat of violent appropriation by the peasants. Grossman (Reference Grossman1995) applies a similar argument to identify the conditions under which a class of capitalists voluntarily agrees to redistribute income to the working class via a tax-financed wage subsidy. Acemoglu and Robinson (Reference Acemoglu and Robinson2000) interpret the extension of voting rights to wider segments of society during the nineteenth century as a strategic commitment to redistribution aimed at preventing a revolution. In Bös and Kolmar (Reference Bös and Kolmar2003), two individuals differ with respect to their initial land possessions, production technology, and appropriation technology. When the time horizon is infinite, a self-enforced, Pareto-improving agreement is possible in which the less productive individual waives his property claims in exchange for a compensatory transfer. More recently, Dal Bó and Dal Bó (Reference Dal Bó and Dal Bó2011) illustrate how policies that are distortionary under the assumption of perfectly secure property rights can be optimal in a second-best world (Lipsey and Lancaster Reference Lipsey and Lancaster1956) of imperfect property rights, in which such policies “buy social peace”.

Within the production, appropriation and defense framework, several experimental studies have explored the emergence of endogenous property rights. Durham et al. (Reference Durham, Hirshleifer and Smith1998) find evidence on the paradox of power (Hirshleifer Reference Hirshleifer1991), i.e. that the initially poorer side will improve its relative position vis-à-vis an initially richer and thus stronger opponent. Carter and Anderton (Reference Carter and Anderton2001) report strong support for the emergence of stable anarchic equilibria as predicted by the predator-prey model of Grossman and Kim (Reference Grossman and Kim1996), in which the degree of (socially wasteful) appropriative activity depends on the relative effectiveness of the predator’s conflict technology compared to the prey’s. In contrast, Duffy and Kim (Reference Duffy and Kim2005) find that large groups struggle to coordinate on anarchic equilibria as players under-invest in defense leading to excessive predation. The presence of a dictator, who imposes a certain level of defense upon the players, allows groups to coordinate on a Pareto-superior equilibrium. In a cross-cultural lab experiment, Ahn et al. (Reference Ahn, Balafoutas, Batsaikhan, Campos-Ortiz, Putterman and Sutter2016) show that secure property rights are more likely to emerge in countries with high levels of trust, and Ahn et al. (Reference Ahn, Loukas, Batsaikhan, Campos-Ortiz, Putterman and Sutter2018) find that communication significantly increases efficiency in a property rights dilemma.

While in the same spirit as those papers, our theoretical framework is more parsimonious, in the interest of keeping the experimental environment sufficiently tractable. First, rather than allowing discrete investments into productive and appropriative activities, our production function relies on a binary action space (claim, concede). Wealth is produced whenever there are secure individual property rights, which occurs when exactly one player claims and the other concedes. Second, our players do not differ in terms of their (production or appropriation) skills but only with respect to their position on the pre-birth status ladder, which defines the relative frequency of being the focal (Schelling Reference Schelling1960) claimant throughout one’s life.

From a more technical vantage point, we relate to the literature on coordination of conflicting interests. Similar to the present paper, Isoni et al. (Reference Isoni, Poulsen, Sugden and Tsutsui2013) interpret successful coordination on the pure equilibria of a highly asymmetric BoS game as “property conventions”. Crawford et al. (Reference Crawford, Gneezy and Rottenstreich2008) show that the power of focality—so effective when players’ interests are perfectly aligned (Mehta et al. Reference Mehta, Starmer and Sugden1994; Bardsley et al. Reference Bardsley, Mehta, Starmer and Sugden2009)—is considerably reduced as soon as payoffs are minimally asymmetric. When payoff asymmetry is very pronounced, i.e. when players differ strongly in their preference ranking over the set of equilibria, even explicit recommendations to play a specific equilibrium fail, leading to substantial efficiency losses (Anbarcı et al. Reference Anbarcı, Feltovich and Gürdal2018). The recommendations fail because they are largely not followed by the players asked to play their less preferred equilibrium. We show that self-enforced redistribution institutions can restore the power of focality.

Several laboratory experiments have documented that—in repeated 2-person BoS games with partner matching—people use shared common history to successfully coordinate on turn-taking equilibria (Rapoport et al. Reference Rapoport, Guyer and Gordon1976; Sonsino and Sirota Reference Sonsino and Sirota2003; Arifovic and Ledyard Reference Arifovic and Ledyard2018), even if it implies ignoring readily available, exogenous correlation devices (Duffy et al. Reference Duffy, Lai and Lim2017). In such turn-taking equilibria, the player who concedes the right of playing her preferred equilibrium to her counterpart, relies on (the expectation of) direct reciprocity to (rightfully) expect being compensated by her counterpart’s conceding in the future. But as social groups become larger and players interact with varying counterparts, it becomes disproportionately more difficult to (a) construct a shared common history and (b) rely on direct reciprocity. The self-enforced redistribution institutions studied in this paper illustrate how the general ideas of concession and compensation can extend to more anonymous settings.

The growing experimental literature on redistribution has almost exclusively focused on the effects of redistribution when property rights are secure. Agranov and Palfrey (Reference Agranov and Palfrey2015) show that when inequality stems from experimentally induced differences in labor productivity, there is an equity-efficiency tradeoff as higher redistribution leads to lower labor supply. Instead, we study a situation without property right enforcement, in which inequality stems from agents being differently privileged in the prevalent order (status quo). Baranski (Reference Baranski2016) studies how redistribution affects individual investment decisions into a common project. He shows that adding a second stage where players redistribute the total value of common production via multilateral bargaining yields much higher levels of efficiency than the typical voluntary contributions mechanism (VCM), in which distribution is exogenously imposed. A notable exception is the game studied by Ryvkin and Semykina (Reference Ryvkin and Semykina2017) where citizens can choose to replace a democratic regime, in which property rights are secure and redistribution requires a majority vote, by an autocrat who promises full redistribution but who can potentially expropriate the citizens. They show that subjects are more likely to voluntarily switch from democracy to autocracy when inequality is high.

The experimental studies of Sausgruber and Tyran (Reference Sausgruber and Tyran2011), Esarey et al. (Reference Esarey, Salmon and Barrilleaux2012), and Durante et al. (Reference Durante, Putterman and van der Weele2014) indicate that redistribution choices in the laboratory are largely in line with observational field data (Fong Reference Fong2001; Alesina and Angeletos Reference Alesina and Angeletos2005; Alesina and Giuliano Reference Alesina and Giuliano2011). Recent work of Cohn et al. (Reference Cohn, Jessen, Klasnja and Smeets2019) confirms the explanatory power of lab methods for understanding the redistributive preferences not only of the general population but also of the economic elite. They report that the richest 5% of the US population is less supportive of redistribution than the bottom 95% because a larger share of the top 5% regards unequal earnings as fair even when the inequality is caused purely by luck. Taking advantage of Swiss direct democracy, Epper et al. (Reference Epper, Fehr and Senn2020) document that preferences elicited in the laboratory predict individuals’ support for redistribution in several national plebiscites.

Section 2 introduces the theoretical framework, followed by the experimental design in Sect. 3. We present our experimental results in Sect. 4 and discuss our findings in Sect. 5.

2 Theoretical framework

We conceptualize society as a group of N players, whose members regularly experience anonymous bilateral encounters with one another, in which they produce wealth by voluntarily agreeing on who claims property of a coveted resource, and who concedes. Players differ only with respect to their position on a pre-birth status ladder. We first explain the stage game and then the supergame, in the absence of redistribution opportunities. We characterize a bourgeois equilibrium in which lower ranks voluntarily concede to higher ranks, and examine the role of zero-sum transfers in sustaining that equilibrium in the presence of behavioral types.

2.1 Stage game

Two members i = 1 , 2 of the society meet and face the question who of the two should own a coveted resource. For each player i, the set of possible actions is A i = { c l a i m , c o n c e d e } . We define a = ( a 1 , a 2 ) as an action profile with a 1 being the action of player 1 (the row player) and a 2 being the action of player 2 (the column player). Each player prefers being the sole claimant (claim, concede) to the other player being the sole claimant (concede, claim) to having unproductive disagreement (claim, claim) or (concede, concede). Figure 1 shows the normal form game G with payoffs x i { 0 , l , h } and 0 < l < h .Footnote 6

Fig. 1 Stage game

The two pure Nash equilibria of G are e 1 = ( c l a i m , c o n c e d e ) and e 2 = ( c o n c e d e , c l a i m ) , where e 1 is the equilibrium more favorable to player 1, and e 2 to player 2.Footnote 7 The mixed equilibrium e mix is constituted by playing the action claim with P mix ( c l a i m ) = h h + l and results in an expected payoff of E mix = hl h + l < l .Footnote 8 The mixed equilibrium is thus unsatisfactory, both from a social and from an individual perspective whereas the two pure equilibria pose a coordination problem in which each of the players will eye her preferred equilibrium.

Potentially, this situation could be resolved with the help of a correlation device (Aumann Reference Aumann1974, Reference Aumann1987). This could for instance be a recommendation of play derived from some prevailing legal or social order, i.e. the status quo. Whenever two players meet, they know who is supposed to claim, and who to concede. For instance, the prevailing order could stipulate who is supposed to claim a certain piece of land (the first-born son of the deceased former owner or the peasant who has worked that land for years). It could also stipulate who is supposed to claim medical treatment at a crowded hospital (the person with the more expensive health plan or the person with the more urgent medical condition).

Definition 1

ϕ = ( M 1 , M 2 , π ) is a direct correlation device, where M i , i = 1 , 2 , is the finite set of messages M i = A i for player i. There is a probability distribution over the set of possible message profiles M = { e 1 , e 2 } with P r o b ( e 1 ) = π and P r o b ( e 2 ) = 1 - π . The device selects a message profile m M according to the probability distribution and privately sends m i to player i.Footnote 9

In the extended game G ϕ , where players receive a message before they play G, the combination of an identical dyadic action space A i for both players and a direct correlation device (Myerson Reference Myerson1994) with mutually exclusive messages leads to the full revelation of the other player’s message given one’s own private message. Thus, when a player receives one of the two possible messages (claim or concede), she knows that her counterpart received the opposite message. As a result, mutually following the device will always end up in one of the pure Nash equilibria.

Definition 2

A bourgeois equilibrium is a pair ( ϕ , σ ) such that the pure strategies σ i : A i A i of the players are identity maps that constitute a Nash equilibrium of the extended game G ϕ .Footnote 10

In this correlated equilibrium, players always comply with whatever is recommended in the status quo: σ i ( a i ) = a i . Following Bhaskar (Reference Bhaskar2000) and Gintis (Reference Gintis2007), we refer to it as the bourgeois equilibrium.Footnote 11

2.2 Supergame

The supergame consists of an indefinite series of random and anonymous two-person encounters within the society of N players. In every encounter, the extended game G ϕ is played. A pre-birth lottery determines a player’s rank in society. The higher (lower) one’s rank, the more often the action recommended by the status quo is to claim (concede). A player’s rank can be understood as a bundle of pre-birth characteristics (gender, ethnicity, inherited wealth, parents’ education, etc.) affecting the frequency of situations in which—in the prevailing social or legal order—an individual is supposed to get a coveted resource, or to accept that somebody else gets it.

Definition 3

Let Θ be an exogenous status hierarchy were θ i { 1 , 2 , , N } denotes the rank of player i in the society such that the lower the number the higher the rank, and no two players can have the exact same rank θ i θ - i . The function ϑ : Θ π induces a message-hierarchy. ϑ chooses the probability π of the direct correlation device ϕ such that a player’s probability to receive her favorable message increases linearly with her rank, i.e. ϑ ( θ i ) = π = N - θ i N - 1 .

The rank of a player is not directly payoff-relevant. But it becomes indirectly payoff relevant through (1) the correlation device favoring higher ranks and (2) the common expectation of compliance with the status quo. The former is due to ϑ determining the probability π of the direct correlation device ϕ such that it sends the message m i = c l a i m more often to player i, the higher i’s rank. The latter, as we have shown above, is true in the bourgeois equilibrium. Thus—in equilibrium—the function ϑ manifests the hierarchical ordering of Θ into a hierarchy of expected payoffs E θ i :

(1) E θ i = h π + l ( 1 - π ) = h ( N - θ i ) + l ( θ i - 1 ) N - 1

In the bourgeois equilibrium, the highest rank θ i = 1 earns x i = h and the lowest rank θ i = N earns x i = l . The other ranks’ expected payoffs fall between these two extremes, strictly (and linearly) decreasing in the rank’s number.

Hypothesis 1

The exogenous status hierarchy translates into a payoff hierarchy.

2.3 Deviations from the bourgeois equilibrium

Potentially, there are many reasons why players would not follow the recommendation. For instance, there could be strategic uncertainty about the counterparts’ level of rationality.Footnote 12 Players may just disregard the device or refuse to follow the recommendation due to some non-standard preferences (DellaVigna Reference DellaVigna2009), for instance, other-regardingness.Footnote 13 There could also be misunderstandings about the direct nature of the device, resulting in ambiguity about the interpretation of the message (Duffy et al. Reference Duffy, Lai and Lim2017). Moreover, beliefs could be strategically distorted (Di Tella et al. Reference Di Tella, Perez-Truglia, Babino and Sigman2015). We subsume all of the above reasons into the potential existence of behavioral types (Embrey et al. Reference Embrey, Frechette and Lehrer2015) who sometimes deviate from the bourgeois equilibrium, and define w j as the probability with which player i expects her counterpart j to deviate in a given encounter.Footnote 14 In the spirit of trembling hand perfection (Selten Reference Selten1975), we then compute tolerance thresholds w ¯ j to determine the maximum deviation propensity that a player would tolerate before starting to deviate herself from the bourgeois equilibrium.

In the supergame, a player is willing to comply and receive E θ i in ( 1 - w j ) of her encounters and zero otherwise as long as complying with the status quo is more profitable than ignoring the device and receiving E mix .Footnote 15 The lower a player’s rank θ i , the less frequently ( π ) she is supposed to claim in the status quo, the less she has to lose from the collapse of the bourgeois equilibrium, the lower her tolerance threshold w ¯ θ i j :

(2) w ¯ θ i j = E θ i - E mix E θ i = 1 - hl h + l [ π h + ( 1 - π ) l ] - 1

The lowest-ranked player’s ( π = 0 ) threshold w ¯ N j = l h + l turns out to be the critical threshold for the existence of the bourgeois equilibrium. If the lowest rank N decides that it pays more to disobey the status quo, this would trigger a chain reaction that reduces the tolerance thresholds of higher-ranked players likewise to w ¯ N j , leading to the collapse of the bourgeois equilibrium. To see this, assume for a moment that the lowest-ranked player systematically disobeyed and always played claim. As a consequence, the second-lowest player N - 1 would see her payoff from the only encounter in which she is higher ranked being reduced from h to 0 (if she continues playing claim) or l (if she disobeys the device herself and plays concede). Her expected payoff would thus be reduced (at least) to E N and her tolerance threshold would drop to:

(3) w ¯ N - 1 j = l h + l = w ¯ N j : = w ¯ crit

Proposition 1

If the common belief w j about the mean disposition to disobey is below w ¯ crit = l h + l , then there exists a bourgeois equilibrium, in which all players comply with the status quo.

2.4 Redistribution

The peril of entering such ruinous dynamic could be mitigated by increasing w ¯ crit . In principle, a simple transfer institution could achieve this. Consider for instance the possibility of making a zero-sum transfer in the immediate aftermath of successful coordination in the stage game.

Definition 4

T is a transfer stage in which players of G ϕ with payoff x i = h can make direct transfers τ i [ 0 , h ] to the other player of G ϕ with payoff x j = l after successful coordination.

A transfer τ in every encounter would flatten the hierarchy of tolerance thresholds against potential deviations in (2). High ranks’ thresholds would go down by the same amount that low ranks’ thresholds go up. As a result, the critical threshold would increase by τ h + l :

(4) w ¯ τ crit = l + τ ( l + τ ) + ( h - τ ) = l + τ h + l

In order to persuade the lowest rank to obey the status quo, high ranks need to transfer τ min w j ( h + l ) - l . Common knowledge about the mean disposition to disobey w j thus translates into common knowledge about τ min . The higher w j , the higher the transfer needed to stabilize the bourgeois equilibrium. If provided, transfers would broaden the set of possible final payoff distributions as shown in Fig. 2. The diagonal line represents the expected payoff distribution in the bourgeois equilibrium with zero transfers. The horizontal line depicts the most extreme form of payoff redistribution (egalitarian optimum).Footnote 16 The shaded area between these two lines is the set of possible bourgeois equilibria reachable with different levels of average transfers. All ranks are better of in any bourgeois equilibrium than in the mixed equilibrium. The higher the rank, the larger the difference.

Fig. 2 Equilibrium payoffs by rank. The dashed horizontal line slightly below l denotes expected payoffs in the mixed equilibrium. The solid diagonal line shows expected payoffs in the bourgeois equilibrium without transfers, ranging from an expected payoff of h for rank 1 to an expected payoff of l for rank N. The shaded area up to the solid horizontal line at h + l 2 shows the bourgeois equilibrium with varying volume of transfers

Hypothesis 2

Transfers increase the incidence of the bourgeois equilibrium.

It can easily be shown that the voluntary provision of τ min can be sustained in equilibrium. If all other players (are commonly expected to) provide exactly τ min , no player has an incentive to unilaterally provide neither more nor less than τ min . A higher transfer would entail additional cost without added benefit since τ min is sufficient to secure perfect obedience of the lowest rank. On the other hand, a lower transfer would fail to reach the critical threshold, triggering the collapse of the bourgeois equilibrium. As shown above, all ranks are worse off in the mixed equilibrium. Thus, no player has a reason to deviate from τ min .

Proposition 2

If the common belief w j about the mean disposition to disobey is below w ¯ crit = 1 2 , there exists a bourgeois equilibrium, in which the transfer τ min is provided and all players comply with the status quo.

3 Experimental design

We conduct a laboratory experiment to test how redistribution affects efficiency via the self-enforcement of property rights, and to identify which status groups benefit more and which less. As laid out in the preceding section, our experimental environment describes an economy with zero coercive means to protect property claims. Status is being exogenously determined in a pre-game lottery, which defines a player’s probability of receiving the recommendation to play claim or concede in a given period.

We compare a baseline treatment (no-T), in which redistributive transfers are not possible, to three treatments with an additional transfer stage. In treatment T-direct players can voluntarily make direct transfers to the person they just interacted with. In T-pool they can voluntarily transfer money to a central pool which is spread equally to all low earners of that period. In T-admin players do not have discretion over their transfers. Instead, transfers are exogenously determined by a random draw from the empirical distribution of T-direct.

The three transfer treatments reflect stylized transfer institutions with varying degrees of centralization, along two dimensions: (a) whether transfers are paid directly to the beneficiary or indirectly, via a central redistribution pool (T-direct vs. T-pool), and (b) whether players have full discretion over the amount they transfer or transfers of the very same amount are exogenously imposed by some central administration (T-direct vs. T-admin).Footnote 17 In the following, we explain the treatments in detail, followed by general experimental procedures and behavioral predictions on expected treatment differences.

3.1 Treatments

no-T. The no-T treatment implements the game G ϕ described in Sect. 2. Subjects are randomly assigned to groups of N = 6 . The composition of the groups is constant over all periods. The paper instructions inform participants that, at the beginning of the experiment, each subject of a given matching group is randomly allocated a unique rank, labeled { a , b , c , d , e , f } from highest to lowest. After the random draw, subjects are informed on their computer screens about their own rank. In every period, subjects are randomly paired within the group and play the 2-player BoS-game of Fig. 1 with h = 10 and l = 1 .Footnote 18 In the experimental instructions, the two actions claim and concede are labeled as red and blue, respectively:

  • If you choose “Red” and the other participant chooses “Blue”, you will earn 10 points, and the other participant will earn 1 point.

  • If you choose “Blue” and the other participant chooses “Red”, you will earn 1 point, and the other participant will earn 10 points.

  • If both participants choose “Red”, you will both earn 0 points.

  • If both participants choose “Blue”, you will both earn 0 points.

The correlation device is introduced through the salient highlighting of one of the two possible color-coded actions, i.e., the relatively higher-ranked (lower-ranked) player of each encounter sees the action red (blue) highlighted in bold letters. This is commonly known to all subjects:

At the beginning of the experiment, the computer will name the participants of each group of six, assigning to each a randomly drawn letter (a, b, c, d, e, or f). [...] Whenever you see the field ’Red’ in bold, the other participant sees the field ’Blue’ in bold, and vice versa. You are free to decide whether you wish to follow the marking or not. The computer decides on the basis of your letter which field is in bold. Whichever participant’s letter comes first in the alphabet sees the field “Red” in bold. Footnote 19

Subjects are not explicitly informed about the absolute rank of their counterpart but can always infer the relative rank from the correlation device. There were no persistent individual identifiers shown to the players. At the end of each period, subjects are informed about the choice of their counterpart and the resulting payoffs. In addition, subjects receive information about how the participants of the other encounters (within the same group) have chosen, and about the total cumulated payoff of all participants (within the same group). The actions and payoffs of the other group members were not indexed by their rank letter (nor any other individual identifier).

T-direct. The T-direct treatment is identical to no-T except that there is now an additional transfer stage (in every period), in which players can simultaneously make direct zero-sum transfers to each other. If a player earned x i = 10 ( x i = 1 ) in G ϕ , she can transfer up to 10 (1) tokens to the player who earned x i = 1 ( x i = 10 ) in G ϕ of the same encounter.Footnote 20

T-pool. The T-pool treatment is identical to no-T except that there is now an additional transfer stage (in every period), in which players can simultaneously make payoff transfers to a fund that is spread evenly among all qualifying players. If a player earned x i = 10 ( x i = 1 ) in G ϕ , she can transfer up to 10 (1) tokens to pool P L ( P H ). Within each group, the sum of transfers to P L ( P H ) is then distributed equally among all players who earned x i = 1 ( x i = 10 ) in that period.

T-admin. In T-admin players cannot choose themselves the amount transferred to their counterpart. Instead, players are informed that the computer will automatically determine a transfer amount. In particular, in each stage game of T-admin, the transfer amount τ i is determined by a random draw from the empirical distribution of transfers in T-direct. For that purpose, all transfer decisions (including the decisions to transfer zero) from T-direct are put into one of 12 urns Υ x θ , depending on the rank θ a , b , c , d , e , f of the transferring player, and her stage-game payoffs x 1 , 10 .Footnote 21 Whenever players in T-admin succesfully coordinate on (red, blue) or on (blue, red) and thus earn payoffs (10, 1) or (1, 10), the experimental software randomly draws (with replacement) a transfer amount from the respective urn. If for instance, b succesfully coordinated with c on (red, blue), the software would draw an amount τ i from urn Υ 10 b to be transferred from b to c, and an amount τ i from urn Υ 1 c to be transferred from c to b.Footnote 22 As a result, transfers in T-admin are virtually identical to transfers in T-direct.Footnote 23 See Figure A5.

3.2 Procedure

Every subject participated in exactly one supergame, which lasted at least 50 periods. To mimic an indefinite time horizon, we use a random continuation rule (Roth and Murnighan Reference Roth and Murnighan1978), closely following the protocol of Camera and Casari (Reference Camera and Casari2009) and Bigoni et al. (Reference Bigoni, Camera and Casari2019). Subjects play 50 periods with certainty, thereafter the continuation probability decreases to δ = 0.75 . Hence, in every period t > 50 , the expected number of additional periods is 3. The exact duration of the supergame was randomly determined for each experimental session. The longest session ended randomly after 60 periods.

All periods played were payoff-relevant, i.e. participants were paid the sum of the earnings of all periods played.Footnote 24 Before the start of the experiment, paper instructions (see “Appendix A.3”) were handed out and read aloud to ensure common knowledge. Additionally, subjects had to pass extensive control questions to ensure full understanding. After the supergame, we elicited participants’ (a) other-regarding preferences, (b) risk and trust attitudes as commonly elicited in the German Socioeconomic Panel (SOEP), (c) some socio-demographics (age, gender, number of siblings). See “Appendix A.4”.

The experiment was conducted at the BonnEconLab of the University of Bonn, Germany, and was computerized using the software z-Tree (Fischbacher Reference Fischbacher2007). From a database of more than 5000 people, we recruited 384 subjects (96 per treatment), using hroot (Bock et al. Reference Bock, Baetge and Nicklisch2014). Each subject participated only in one treatment (between-subject design). Subjects were mainly undergraduate students from a variety of disciplines. Sessions lasted about 90 min and subjects earned on average 18.01 € (about 22.00 $) including a show-up fee of 4 €. During the experiment, payoffs where presented in experimental currency units (ECU), with a known exchange rate of ECU 25 = 1 €. Subjects sat in visually completely isolated cubicles.

3.3 Behavioral predictions

The goal of the experiment is to test how redistribution affects efficiency via the self-enforcement of property rights, and to compare the effectiveness of different ways to organize redistribution, varying in their degree of centralization. In the following, we discuss how the different institutional settings are likely to perform depending on the relative strength of several plausible behavioral mechanisms.

As detailed in Sect. 2, if there is reluctance to follow the correlation device because of the resulting payoff asymmetry (10, 1), we should observe substantial miscoordination in the baseline noT. Transfer institutions enable the high earners to reduce inequality and thus increase low earners’ willingness to coordinate on the bourgeois equilibrium (i.e. choose red when red is shown in bold, and choose blue when blue is shown in bold). In T-direct, the earner of 10 can make a transfer to the earner of 1 after successful coordination. Even though the high earner benefits from increasing the probability with which the low earner will concede in a future encounter, she has an incentive to free ride on the transfers of other high earners. Given the lack of persistent individual identifiers, transfers cannot be used to spark and sustain cycles of direct reciprocity (Gintis Reference Gintis2000; Fehr and Gächter Reference Fehr and Gächter2000; Fehr et al. Reference Fehr, Fischbacher and Gächter2002).

We compare the effectiveness of T-direct, in which transfers are paid directly to the beneficiary, to T-pool, in which transfers are paid indirectly, via a central redistribution pool. Within the rational choice framework of Sect. 2, the transfers schemes of T-direct and T-pool do not differ in their incentive structure. Both pose the exact same problem of collective action. Behaviorally, however, they could differ. In fact, whether subjects are more willing to provide transfers in T-direct or in T-pool might depend on whether high earners conceptualize the decision to transfer from a backward-looking or from a forward-looking perspective.

From a backward-looking perspective, a transfer would be given to reward the behavior of one’s recent counterpart; i.e. to return either trust or the favor of a gift exchange (Berg et al. Reference Berg, Dickhaut and McCabe1995; Fehr et al. Reference Fehr, Kirchsteiger and Riedl1998; McCabe et al. Reference McCabe, Rassenti and Smith1996; Gächter and Falk Reference Gächter and Falk2002; Engelmann and Ortmann Reference Engelmann and Ortmann2002). In this case, the T-direct mechanism should trigger higher willingness to transfer since it allocates the entire amount to the person targeted whereas the mechanism of T-pool dilutes the expression of gratitude, and diffuses the responsibility (Dana et al. Reference Dana, Weber and Kuang2007; Hamman et al. Reference Hamman, Loewenstein and Weber2010; Bartling et al. Reference Bartling, Weber and Yao2014) for rewarding the obedient lower rank. From a forward-looking perspective, a transfer would be given as an investment into the future obedience of a likely interaction partner; i.e. as an attempt to initiate a cycle of indirect reciprocity (Alexander Reference Alexander1987; Boyd and Richerson Reference Boyd and Richerson1989; Dufwenberg et al. Reference Dufwenberg, Gneezy, Güth and Van Damme2001; Greiner and Levati Reference Greiner and Levati2005; Nowak and Sigmund Reference Nowak and Sigmund2005). In this case, the T-pool mechanism is more appealing since it hedges the investment risk between several possible future counterparts.

In sum, we should observe higher average transfers and better coordination in T-direct (T-pool) if the backward-looking (forward-looking) perspective dominates. In addition, even if average transfers in T-direct and T-pool were identical, some high earners are likely to be more generous than others. The T-pool mechanism smooths out the period-by-period variation of the transfers received by individual low-ranked players, making it easier for players to learn the expected average transfer, potentially enabling them to reach the equilibrium faster.Footnote 25

Finally, we compare a setting in which players have full discretion over the amount they transfer (T-direct) to one in which transfers of the very same amount are exogenously imposed by some central administration (T-admin). If only distributional concerns mattered, we should see no difference between both treatments as average transfer levels are identical by design. However, transfers between T-admin and T-direct could differ if indirect reciprocity matters. In T-admin, players cannot reciprocate to receiving transfers since the transfers are exogenous (Charness and Rabin Reference Charness and Rabin2002; Falk et al. Reference Falk, Fehr and Fischbacher2008). Whether transfers in T-direct trigger positive or rather negative indirect reciprocity will depend on the low earner’s perception of the transfer received relative to what she deems appropriate. If the average transfer level is perceived positively (i.e. more than appropriate), low ranks will express their gratitude by conceding more in T-direct than in T-admin. On the other hand, if the average transfer level is perceived negatively (i.e. less than appropriate), low ranks will express their dissatisfaction by conceding less in T-direct than in T-admin. In addition, players in T-direct could be tempted to strategically withhold conceding (Schelling Reference Schelling1956; Crawford Reference Crawford1982), particularly early in the game, in an attempt to press the high ranks for more generous transfers. Strategic considerations are pointless in T-admin.

4 Results

We first report how redistribution affects overall efficiency and the economic status of different ranks. Subsequently, we look into subjects’ willingness to concede to higher-ranked players and their willingness to transfer money to lower-ranked players as the behavioral drivers of treatment differences.

4.1 Payoffs

Figure 3 shows the development of efficiency over time, in payoff units. While the no-T treatment generates substantially more wealth than the mixed equilibrium, it achieves only 47% of the payoffs attainable in the bourgeois equilibrium. With redistribution, efficiency improves to 67% in T-direct (p = .003) and 64% in T-pool (p = .016) but still falls significantly short of the bourgeois equilibrium prediction. In the first 15 periods, all three transfer treatments display a noticeable increase in efficiency whereas the no-T treatment does not. From period 15 on, payoffs in T-direct and T-pool stagnate at or below 70 % . In contrast, coordination in T-admin continues to rise throughout the duration of the supergame, averaging 85 % in the last 10 periods, significantly higher than T-direct (p = .041) despite having—by design—the same level of transfers.Footnote 26

All these observed treatment differences emerge over time. In period 1, there are no significant differences between no-T and any of the transfer treatments ( p > . 182 ). Neither is there a difference between T-direct and T-admin (p = .183). Interestingly, initial coordination (and thus efficiency) is weakly higher in T-pool than in T-direct (p = .086). But this difference vanishes over time.

Fig. 3 Payoffs over time. Mean payoffs after transfers. The solid (dashed) horizontal line at 5.5 (.9) denotes predicted average payoffs in the bourgeois equilibrium (mixed equilibrium). The 95% confidence intervals capture the between-group variation around the treatment means

Result 1

Transfer institutions lead to better coordination and thus higher efficiency. Exogenously administered transfers are the most effective.

Figure 4 shows payoffs over time separately for the lower ranks ( d - f ) and the upper ranks ( a - c ). Panel A shows that for the lower half of the status hierarchy, the exact design of the transfer institution is immaterial. The large payoff difference concerns the presence or absence of some (any) transfer institution. In contrast, for the upper half the exact design matters a lot. Players who were given high status in the pre-play lottery benefit considerably from not having discretion over the amount they transfer. The difference between T-admin and T-direct begins to emerge around period 15 and continues to grow toward the end of the game. In the last 10 periods, upper ranks earn 26 percent more in T-admin than in T-direct (p = .026).Footnote 27

Result 2

Upper ranks benefit from not having discretion over the amount they transfer. For the lower ranks, the exact design of the transfer institution is immaterial.

Fig. 4 Payoffs over time—lower vs. upper ranks. Mean payoffs after transfers, for A ranks d - f , B ranks a - c . The solid (dashed) horizontal line at 5.5 (.9) denotes predicted average payoffs in the bourgeois equilibrium with maximum redistribution (mixed equilibrium). The 95% confidence intervals capture the between-group variation around the treatment means

In Fig. 5 we disaggregate the treatment effects even further, to identify individual ranks and compare payoffs before (left) and after (right) transfers. The dashed black line at .9 shows the predicted payoffs in the mixed equilibrium: such a society would be poor but egalitarian. In contrast, the average group of the no-T treatment is significantly richer ( p < . 001 ) and displays a pronounced payoff hierarchy. The higher a player’s rank, the higher her payoff.Footnote 28 Moreover, no rank is worse off than in the mixed equilibrium. Each rank a - d earns significantly more than the mixed equilibrium ( p < . 049 ) payoff.

Fig. 5 Effect of redistribution on payoff, by ranks. Mean payoffs before (left) and after (right) transfers, averaged over AB periods 1–50 or CD periods 41–50. The dashed horizontal line at .9 denotes expected payoffs in the mixed equilibrium. The solid diagonal line shows expected payoffs in the bourgeois equilibrium without transfers. The solid horizontal line at 5.5 shows the bourgeois equilibrium with maximum volume of transfers. The 95% confidence intervals capture the between-group variation around the treatment means

There are four interesting observations. First, the availability of transfer institutions flattens the payoff hierarchy. The Gini coefficient drops from .30 in no-T to about .18 in the transfer treatments ( p < . 002 ).Footnote 29 But even after transfers, the distribution of payoffs is far from flat but still conditioned by the draw of luck that determines a player’s position on the status ladder. Second, lower ranks not only benefit directly from the institutional environment—through the net transfers received—but also indirectly—through the reduction of miscoordination. In fact, compared to the no-T treatment, in each of the transfer treatments net recipients d ( p < . 006 ) and e ( p < . 023 ) would already be significantly better off before transfers, i.e. solely through the reduction of disputes over claims. Rank f, however, is only better off after transfers ( p < . 001 ). Third, no rank (not even a) is better off without rather than with transfer institutions. Averaged over all periods, even net contributors b ( p < . 055 ) and c ( p < . 003 ) have substantially higher after-transfer payoffs in T-direct and T-admin than in no-T. Fourth, no rank loses from transfers being exogenously imposed rather than voluntary. Zooming in on the last 10 periods, we see that the dashed purple T-admin line is consistently above the solid red T-direct line. The main beneficiaries of that lack of discretion are in fact ranks b (p = .013) and c (p = .032).

Result 3

The exogenous status hierarchy translates into a hierarchy of payoffs, even after transfers.

Result 4

Lower ranks benefit both directly from the presence of transfer institutions—through the transfers received—and indirectlythrough the reduction of miscoordination.

4.2 Compliance with the status quo

In the bourgeois equilibrium, players are predicted to follow the correlation device and thus choose the action claim when the message is claim, and to concede when told to concede. The critical condition for the existence of the bourgeois equilibrium is the lowest-ranked player’s belief about others’ disposition to obey the recommendation of the correlation device. In the absence of transfers (Proposition Footnote 1), rank f needs to believe that others will obey with at least 91% probability (and disobey with 9% probability). In the presence of transfers (Proposition Footnote 2), she only needs an obedience belief of 50%. In Figure A2, we plot the relative frequency of full coordination on the bourgeois equilibrium in the last 10 periods against the mean obedience of others, as experienced by rank f in the first 40 periods.Footnote 30 We find that in the no-T treatment, 7 of 16 groups do not satisfy the condition. In the three transfer treatments (T-direct, T-pool, and T-admin), only 1 of 48 groups does not satisfy the critical condition. In all four treatments there is a strong positive correlation between the mean obedience experienced by rank f in the first 40 periods and the relative frequency of full coordination on the bourgeois equilibrium in the last 10 periods.Footnote 31

Figure 6 shows the conditional probabilities for (a) claiming and (b) conceding in the different treatments. Across all treatments, and for all ranks, the propensity to claim when told to claim (i.e. to choose red when it shown in bold) is around 90%, corroborating the findings of Anbarcı et al. (Reference Anbarcı, Feltovich and Gürdal2018). In contrast, the willingness to concede when told to concede (i.e. to choose blue when it shown in bold) appears to substantially vary with rank. In no-T, the higher a player’s rank, the higher her willingness to concede when told to do so, ranging from 63% for rank b to 34% for f (p = .023).Footnote 32 This is in line with the idea that a player is more willing to abide by a given order, the higher her expected benefits from the order’s existence. Or put differently, a deviation from the bourgeois equilibrium is less likely, the higher a player’s expected cost from the deviation.

Fig. 6 Compliance with the status quo. Mean relative frequency of complying with the exogenous recommendation when one’s message is A claim (i.e. red field shown in bold) or B concede (i.e. blue field shown in bold). The solid (dashed) horizontal line denotes predicted behavior in the bourgeois equilibrium (mixed equilibrium). The 95% confidence intervals capture the between-group variation around the treatment means

Yet interestingly, this logic does not seem to translate to the transfer treatments. In fact, we find the entire positive effect of transfer institutions on conceding to be driven by the bottom ranks. Compared to the no-T treatment, conceding of rank f increases by 24 percentage points in T-direct and T-pool ( p < . 033 ), respectively, and by additional 20 percentage points in T-admin (p = .067). For rank e the increase is 32–39 percentage points ( p < . 007 ). For rank d there is a significant rise in conceding of 25 percentage points in T-direct and T-admin ( p < . 008 ) but no effect in T-pool. In contrast, the willingness to concede (i.e. to choose blue when it shown in bold) of ranks b and c is virtually unaffected by the presence of redistribution.Footnote 33

Since transfers in T-admin and T-direct were virtually identical, both over ranks and over time (see Figure A5), the observed difference between both treatments reveals the importance of motives for withholding conceding beyond purely distributional concerns. As noted in Sect. 3.3, plausible arguments for T-admin generating higher levels of conceding could be the absence of strategic reasons to withhold conceding, and less dissatisfaction with disappointing transfers coming from an impersonal process rather than from another human being. Arguably, differences in dissatisfaction should rather play out at later stages of the game when players have learned the typical level of transfers. In contrast, if lower ranks were strategically withholding their conceding in order to squeeze out higher transfers later in the game, we should rather observe contrasting patterns in the early stages of the game.

Individual patterns of conceding over time (Figure A3), show that (a) in both treatments there is a decreasing share of individuals who—within blocks of 5 periods—play the mixed strategy sometimes concede. (b) In T-direct, there is a higher share of individuals who play the pure strategy never concede throughout the game (p = .083). (c) The share of always conceders increases in both treatments until period 30 but then plateaus slightly below 60% in T-direct while continuing to rise to 80% in T-admin. In the last 10 periods of the game, the share of always conceders in T-admin is significantly higher than in T-direct (p = .028). The divergence of conceding patterns in the later stages of the game suggests differences in dissatisfaction as the main behavioral channel for the higher effectiveness of T-admin compared to T-direct.

Result 5

Exogenously administered, compulsory redistribution increases lower ranks willingness to concede stronger that discretionary transfers.

4.3 Effect of transfers

Mean transfers are significantly larger in T-direct than in T-pool (p = .046) as only 10% (9 of 87) of players give exactly zero throughout the entire game in T-direct, compared to 26% (23 of 89) in T-pool (p = .008).Footnote 34 The gap is driven by the willingness to transfer of the lower ranks. In particular, rank d (p = .002) and e (p = .044) transfer significantly more in T-direct than in T-pool. In fact, in T-direct the two lower ranks give significantly higher transfers (p = .038) than the three upper ranks. Both the fact that transfers are higher in T-direct than in T-pool, and that—within T-direct—lower ranks are more generous than higher ranks, resonates with the idea that subjects conceive the decision to transfer from a backward-looking (rather than a forward-looking) perspective.Footnote 35 Transfer behavior is very stable over time.

From the perspective of the transfer recipients, transfers in T-direct and T-pool not only differ in terms of their level but also in terms of their period-by-period variation (see Figure A6). As expected, the central pooling mechanism reduces the standard deviation (SD) of received transfers from 1.27 in T-direct to .70 in T-pool ( p < . 001 ) as idiosyncratic differences in high-ranks’ generosity are ironed out. On the other hand, received transfers in T-admin have a higher period-by-period variation (SD = 1.71) than in T-direct ( p < . 001 ) as transfers in all groups of T-admin were drawn from the same empirical distribution, which included the most generous and the most tightfisted individuals from T-direct.

Fig. 7 Transfers and conceding, by groups. Each dot depicts one group. There are 16 groups per treatment. Mean transfer given by the player earning x i = h , and P ( a = c o n c e d e | m = c o n c e d e ) , the mean propensity of conceding when receiving the message concede (i.e. choose blue when blue field is shown in bold), averaged over all ranks. A For all 50 periods, and B for the last 10 periods of the game. The solid red (dashed blue) positive-slope line depicts the simple linear regression in T-direct (T-pool), with 95% confidence intervals. Regression line for T-admin not included because it is insignificantly different from zero (p = .666 and p = .554). The solid (dashed) black horizontal line denotes predicted behavior in the bourgeois equilibrium (mixed equilibrium)

In this game, transfers as such are zero-sum by design.Footnote 36 But indirectly they can contribute to higher overall efficiency if they lead to more conceding, and thus higher rates of coordination. Panel A of Fig. 7 shows that within each of the two endogenous transfer treatments T-direct and T-pool, groups with higher average transfers indeed tend to achieve a higher willingness to concede (i.e. to choose blue when blue is shown in bold).Footnote 37 A simple OLS regression on this highly aggregated data reveals an intercept of .42 (p = .005) and a slope of .13 (p = .049) for T-direct, as well as an intercept of .46 ( p < . 001 ) and a slope of .11 (p = .071) for T-pool. A group with zero transfers is thus predicted to have a willingness to concede of about 44%, which happens to correspond exactly to the mean level of conceding observed in the no-T treatment (see Table A1). This suggests that the mere availability of transfer opportunities has no effect on coordination but instead whether and how transfers are used. As the average transfer volume in a group increases by 1 point, conceding increases by about 12 percentage points. The same pattern holds when looking at the last 10 periods only.Footnote 38 In fact, several groups manage to converge to perfect conceding as predicted in the bourgeois equilibrium, with rather diverse levels of transfers: one group in no-T, two in T-direct, three in T-pool, and six in T-admin. The stark difference between T-direct and T-admin underlines how much more effective redistribution is when administered exogenously. And yet, in all treatments, most groups fail to reach the bourgeois equilibrium, thus foregoing the chance at substantial (material) Pareto improvements.

While the observed positive correlation between transfers and conceding is indeed consistent with our theoretical conjecture that (1) higher transfers lead to higher conceding, it could, in principle, also reflect two other causal relationships: (2) higher conceding is rewarded by higher transfers, and (3) the same individual traits determine both a player’s willingness to transfer and her willingness to concede. To shed some additional light on the underlying behavioral channel, we take advantage of the panel structure of our experimental data, and of the fact that both the players’ ranks as well as the matching of players into groups and encounters were determined exogenously.

Column (1a) of Table 1 presents evidence on how lower ranks’ ( d - f ) individual willingness to concede in the last 10 periods of the game can be explained by upper ranks’ ( a - c ) mean transfers in the first 10 periods of the game. For T-direct, we find that when upper ranks’ mean transfer in the early periods was 1 token higher, the lower rank’s likelihood of conceding in the late periods is about 13 percentage points higher. This holds similarly for T-pool. In contrast, early transfers have no impact on late conceding in T-admin.Footnote 39 This suggests that it is not the early transfers per se that explain the late conceding. Rather, early transfers in T-direct and T-pool reflect a general (i.e. home-grown) willingness to transfer of the upper ranks within a given group, which lower-ranks could learn over the course of the game. In T-admin early transfers within a given group did, by design, not reveal anything about the level of later transfers in that particular group since the transfers of all groups were randomly drawn from the same distribution.Footnote 40 Column (1b) of Table 1 shows that the effect of transfers on conceding is robust to controlling for individual characteristics of the lower ranked players.Footnote 41 In fact, as shown in Columns (2a) and (2b), the effect is even present—albeit weaker—when restricting the explanatory variable Transfer k , upper first η periods to the first period of the game. In period 1, upper ranks’ transfers are uninfluenced by group dynamics, and thus exogenous to lower ranks’ individual willingness to concede in the last 10 periods. Consequently, upper ranks’ mean transfer in period 1 can be interpreted as a home-grown disposition.

Columns (3–4) of Table 1 examine the opposite causal direction, i.e. how upper ranks’ individual willingness to concede in the last 10 periods of the game can be explained by lower ranks’ mean conceding in the first 10 periods of the game. However, we find no evidence for a positive effect of early conceding on later transfers.Footnote 42 Instead, we find upper-ranks’ transfers to be substantially driven by individuals’ Social Value Orientaion (SVO). Ceteris paribus, the transfer of a prototypically pro-social individual ( SVO = 1 ) is, on average, about .7 tokens higher than of a selfish individual ( S V O = 0 ). In sum, controlling for individual traits, we find evidence for higher transfers leading to higher conceding but not for higher conceding being rewarded with higher transfers.

Result 6

Higher transfers lead to more conceding, and thus better coordination and higher efficiency.

Table 1 Willingness to concede and to transfer

DV: Conceding i , lower last 10 periods

DV: Transfer i , upper last 10 periods

(1a)

(1b)

(2a)

(2b)

(3a)

(3b)

(4a)

(4b)

T - pool

- 0.113

- 0.125

- 0.119

- 0.159

0.056

- 0.315

0.900

0.567

(0.168)

(0.168)

(0.169)

(0.168)

(1.194)

(1.094)

(0.951)

(0.851)

T - admin

0.574***

0.503**

0.287**

0.232*

0.870

1.066

0.011

- 0.014

(0.198)

(0.241)

(0.120)

(0.134)

(0.961)

(0.849)

(0.396)

(0.410)

Transfer k , upper first η periods

0.135***

0.128**

0.101***

0.078**

(0.047)

(0.049)

(0.030)

(0.033)

Transfer k , upper first η periods × T - pool

0.022

0.014

- 0.008

0.001

(0.058)

(0.057)

(0.055)

(0.055)

Transfer k , upper first η periods × T - admin

- 0.227**

- 0.206*

- 0.097**

- 0.090*

(0.089)

(0.108)

(0.043)

(0.048)

Conceding k , lower first η periods

0.676

0.437

- 0.867*

- 0.674

(1.431)

(1.190)

(0.447)

(0.480)

Conceding k , lower first η periods × T - pool

- 0.526

- 0.167

- 1.198

- 1.002

(1.955)

(1.816)

(1.220)

(1.103)

Conceding k , lower first η periods × T - admin

- 0.775

- 1.207

0.744

0.540

(1.517)

(1.310)

(0.503)

(0.536)

SVO i

0.051

0.027

0.782**

0.654**

(0.041)

(0.046)

(0.314)

(0.273)

Trust i

0.058

0.073

0.507

0.535

(0.104)

(0.121)

(0.432)

(0.455)

Risk i

- 0.042

- 0.027

- 0.139

0.013

(0.077)

(0.072)

(0.358)

(0.347)

Age i

- 0.006

- 0.012*

- 0.003

- 0.002

(0.006)

(0.006)

(0.017)

(0.017)

Female i

0.041

0.067

- 0.271

- 0.200

(0.059)

(0.071)

(0.268)

(0.247)

Siblings i

0.059*

0.065*

0.030

0.024

(0.033)

(0.034)

(0.081)

(0.080)

Constant

0.476***

0.478***

0.561***

0.590***

1.055

1.282

1.925***

1.936***

(0.127)

(0.140)

(0.097)

(0.110)

(0.893)

(0.834)

(0.362)

(0.387)

Individuals i

144

144

132

132

140

140

140

140

Groups k

48

48

44

44

48

48

48

48

R 2

0.261

0.303

0.146

0.206

0.045

0.165

0.109

0.201

OLS regression. Robust standard errors, clustered by groups, in parentheses. ( p < 0.1 ), ( p < 0.05 ), ( p < 0.01 ). Includes data from T-pool, T-admin, and T-direct, the latter being the reference treatment. Columns 1–2: The DV Conceding i , lower last 10 periods denotes the mean willingness to concede of a lower-rank player i of group k in the last 10 periods of the game (i.e. choose blue when blue field is shown in bold). The explanatory variable Transfer k , upper early denotes the mean transfer given by the upper-rank players of group k in the first η periods, with η = 10 in Column 1 and η = 1 in Column 2. Columns 3–4: The DV Transfer i , upper last 10 periods denotes the mean transfer given by an upper-rank player i of group k in the last 10 periods of the game. The explanatory variable Conceding k , lower early denotes the mean propensity of conceding by the lower-rank players of group k in the first η periods, with η = 10 in Column 3 and η = 1 in Column 4. Ranks a - c ( d - f ) are defined as upper (lower) ranks. The maximum num. of obs. is 144 (3 treatments × 16 groups × 3 encounters). Observations are missing when the DV or one of the explanatory variables is not defined (e.g. when coordination failed and transfers were not possible). See “Appendix A.4”, and Tables A2 and A3 for details on the individual characteristics

5 Conclusion

This paper provides first causal empirical evidence for the conjecture that redistribution can have a positive effect on economic efficiency by reducing disputes over individual property rights. In our experiment, redistribution not only increases overall efficiency but improves the economic status of each rank on the pre-birth status ladder. While lower ranks benefit equally from each of the three stylized transfer institutions studied, upper ranks benefit most from the setting in which the transfer decision is taken out of their hands. Typically, compulsory redistribution is justified as a means to limit temptations to free-ride on other people’s charitableness. Our findings suggest an additional rationale: By mitigating the dissatisfaction from receiving disappointing transfers, non-discretionary redistribution is more effective at persuading lower ranks to obey the rules of the status quo. As a result, the main beneficiaries of exogenously administered transfers happen to be the upper ranks, who lose discretion but gain more secure claims to property. In the absence of coercive means, redistribution serves as a tool to turn privilege into economic payoff by enhancing the power of focality.

We thus add to the strand of research examining the circumstances under which redistribution enhances efficiency (e.g. Eaton and White (Reference Eaton and White1991), Bowles and Gintis (Reference Bowles and Gintis1995), Birdsall et al. (Reference Birdsall, Ross and Sabot1995), Midgley (Reference Midgley1999), see Putterman et al. (Reference Putterman, Roemer and Silvestre1998) for an overview of the literature). We also complement a prominent strand of literature in public economics that has identified negative behavioral responses to redistribution, like lower effort and wasteful expenditures for avoidance. That literature typically assumes that property rights are being enforced, and focuses on individual differences in productivity and effort as drivers of inequality (Agranov and Palfrey Reference Agranov and Palfrey2015). In contrast, we assume zero coercion, and view (the absence of conflict over) property rights as the outcome of some implicit negotiation process between individuals who differ only in terms of their pre-birth privilege in the prevailing social order (status quo). To draw a more realistic picture of the net effect of redistribution on economic efficiency, further research should aim at systematically combining both stylized perspectives. Moreover, a comprehensive assessment of the merits of redistribution needs to consider its implications on expenditures for law enforcement and private protection (Anderson Reference Anderson1999; Merlo Reference Merlo2003) as well as for conspicuous consumption (Hopkins and Kornienko Reference Hopkins and Kornienko2004, Reference Hopkins and Kornienko2009).

In our experimental setting, inequality is not inevitable. Even in the absence of transfer institutions, players could in principle reconcile efficiency and equality, for instance by following the device’s recommendation in odd-numbered periods and doing the opposite in even-numbered periods.Footnote 43 The rank of a player is not directly payoff-relevant but it becomes indirectly payoff relevant through the correlation device systematically favoring higher ranks and the common expectation of compliance with the device.

In reality, of course, pre-birth status differences manifest themselves more directly through differences in resource endowments. Purely exogenous attributes like descent, primogeniture, ethnicity, and gender have historically played a major role in defining status differences concerning the access to resources, e.g. a certain piece of land, the right to exercise a certain profession, the right to vote, and other privileges or property rights (Elster Reference Elster1992; Schotter and Sopher Reference Schotter and Sopher2003; Moulin Reference Moulin2004). Inherited differences in endowments continue to heavily influence a person’s lifetime earnings in many modern democracies, and are often reinforced by differential access to education and the ability to hedge against life risks (Bowles and Gintis Reference Bowles and Gintis2002; Kahlenberg Reference Kahlenberg2010; Chetty et al. Reference Chetty, Hendren, Kline and Saez2014; Adermon et al. Reference Adermon, Lindahl and Waldenström2018). Moreover, differences in initial endowments may come along with the power to coerce others and to bend the rules of the game to one’s advantage, for instance through bribes, control of media outlets and armed non-state actors (Glaeser et al. Reference Glaeser, Scheinkman and Shleifer2003; Acemoglu et al. Reference Acemoglu, Naidu, Restrepo and Robinson2015). By contrast, this paper illustrates the emergence of inequality by much softer means, namely the mere expectation of compliance with a hierarchical status quo.

Funding

Open Access funding enabled and organized by Projekt DEAL.

Footnotes

Electronic supplementary material The online version of this article (https://doi.org/10.1007/s10683-020-09685-5) contains supplementary material, which is available to authorized users.

We thank Ernesto Dal Bó, Marco Casari, Christoph Engel, Willemien Kets, Oliver Kirchkamp, Tatiana Kornienko, Ulrike Malmendier, Isabel Marcin, Moti Michaeli, Rosemarie Nagel, J. J. Prescott, Daniel Salicath, Cornelius Schneider, Sebastian Siegloch, and Theresa Wenning, as well as seminar participants at U Bayreuth, U Marburg, U Passau, and LMU Munich for valuable comments on earlier versions of the paper. Financial support of the Max Planck Society is gratefully acknowledged.

1 For the purpose of clarity, we distinguish between a person’s status as the degree of innate privilege in the prevailing social order, and her economic status as her position in the distribution of income (Bowles and Gintis Reference Bowles and Gintis2002).

2 According to the World Prison Brief of the University of London, the US has an incarceration rate of 655 per 100,000 inhabitants. For comparison, the UK has 148, Germany 77. See https://www.prisonstudies.org/highest-to-lowest/prison_population_rate?field_region_taxonomy_tid=All.

3 The 108 victimizations include only non-violent property crimes like burglaries, residential trespassing, motor-vehicle thefts, and other thefts. In addition, many violent crimes are also property related. For 2018, the DOJ reports 2.1 instances of violent robbery and 18.4 assaults (excluding rape and sexual assault) per 1000 individuals age 12 or older. See http://www.bjs.gov/index.cfm?ty=pbdetail&iid=6686. Exploiting spatial and temporal variation of land titles in the Brazilian Amazon between 1997 and 2010, Fetzer and Marden (Reference Fetzer and Marden2017) document the effect of insecure property rights on land-related violence, attributing 280 murders directly to land disputes.

4 In this theoretical framework, property rights are thus not a constraint but an outcome. For a similar perspective on property rights, see Grossman and Kim (Reference Grossman and Kim1995); Grossman (Reference Grossman2001), and more recently Diermeier et al. (Reference Diermeier, Egorov and Sonin2017).

5 From a bargaining perspective (Schelling Reference Schelling1956; Crawford Reference Crawford1982), the bourgeois equilibrium can be understood as a self-enforced social contract (Binmore Reference Binmore1998), in which the members of a society have reached a (tacit) agreement about the appropriate compensation for waving one’s own claim, in exchange for conceding possession to whoever is higher on the status ladder. Transfers expand the contract zone, i.e. the set of possible agreements. Possession becomes property by mutual acceptance (Bös and Kolmar Reference Bös and Kolmar2003).

6 In some real-world examples, (concede, concede) may be preferable to (claim, claim). Increasing the payoff of (concede, concede) to l instead of 0 does not affect the general structure of the game, see “Appendix A.2”.

7 Note that in this conception of the BoS, players coordinate by choosing different actions.

8 The probabilities of the different outcomes in the mixed equilibrium are: P ( c l a i m , c l a i m ) = h 2 ( h + l ) 2 , P ( c l a i m , c o n c e d e ) = hl ( h + l ) 2 , P ( c o n c e d e , c l a i m ) = hl ( h + l ) 2 and P ( c o n c e d e , c o n c e d e ) = l 2 ( h + l ) 2 . Disagreement is defined as playing either (claim, claim) or (concede, concede). The probability of disagreement is thus h 2 + l 2 ( h + l ) 2 .

9 Both the definition of the extended game and of the correlated equilibrium closely follow the notation of Duffy et al. (Reference Duffy, Lai and Lim2017).

10 A bourgeois equilibrium corresponds to a direct correlated equilibrium following (Aumann Reference Aumann1974, Reference Aumann1987).

11 In an infinitely repeated, symmetric, 2-person BoS game, Bhaskar (Reference Bhaskar2000) distinguishes between an egalitarian convention, in which players use successful (lucky) coordination in the initial period to tacitly agree on alternating between both stage-game equilibria in all subsequent periods, and a bourgeois convention, in which players tacitly agree on sticking with the initial stage-game equilibrium forever.

12 For example Rosenthal (Reference Rosenthal1989) assumes in his bounded-rationality approach that best replies need only be played with a larger probability than other strategies, but not necessarily with probability 1.

13 Note that (1) aversion to advantageous inequality (triggered by earning h and the other player l) decreases the distance in utility space between monetary payoffs h and 0. (2) Aversion to disadvantageous inequality (when earning l and the other player h) decreases the distance between l and 0. (3) People dislike disadvantageous inequality more than advantageous inequality. As a result, for inequality averse players, the difference between h and l is even larger in utility space than in monetary payoff space. See, for instance, Fehr and Schmidt (Reference Fehr and Schmidt1999) and Charness and Rabin (Reference Charness and Rabin2002).

14 Note that for the belief w j it is immaterial whether a given individual deviates deterministically (refusing to ever play the bourgeois equilibrium) or probabilistically (randomizing over the action space). Rather, w j captures the mean disposition to deviate in the population.

15 E ( a i = m i ) ≥ E ( P mix ( c l a i m ) ) ⇒ w j 0 + ( 1 - w j ) E θ i ≥ E mix . For a detailed analysis of deviations in the stage game, see “Appendix A.1”.

16 The highest reasonable transfer is τ max = h - l 2 , which would result in all players having equal payoffs. Transfers beyond τ max would create new inequality by reversing the rank hierarchy. τ max allows to stabilize the bourgeois equilibrium when the mean disposition to disobey is w ¯ max crit = 1 2 . If w j were even larger than w ¯ max crit , transfers would not be able to stabilize the equilibrium.

17 In reality, those institutional differences are generally not ceteris paribus. Rather, transfer institutions that vary in terms of centralization, tend to also differ in other aspects, most notably, their degree of coercion, and of administrative efficiency. We deliberately keep those aspects constant.

18 With these parameters, the highest rank (i.e. the richest 17th percentile) earns 10 times more than the lowest rank (i.e. the poorest 17th percentile) in the bourgeois equilibrium before transfers. This hierarchy of expected payoffs approximates roughly the current income disparity in Germany, where the experiment was conducted. In Germany, the richest 17 percent of the population earn about 12 times more than the poorest 17 percent. For comparison, in the United States the richest 17 percent earn about 50 times more than the poorest 17 percent. Pre-tax income figures from the World Inequality Database: https://wid.world/.

19 See “Appendix A.3”.

20 Note that, in addition to transfers from x i = 10 to x i = 1 players, our experimental design also allowed, in principle, transfers from x i = 1 players to x i = 10 players (see “Appendix A.3”). We chose not to preclude the latter in order to keep the transfer stage as normatively neutral as possible. Empirically however, those x i = 1 to x i = 10 transfers are negligible as they account for only 84 / 3417 = 2.5 % and 80 / 2471 = 3.2 % of all tokens transferred in T-direct and T-pool, respectively.

21 When payoffs are zero, transfers are not possible.

22 Remember that the experimental design of T-direct also allowed transfers from x i = 1 players to x i = 10 players. Despite that case being empirically irrelevant (virtually all entries in Υ 1 θ are zero), we account for it to keep the experimental instructions of T-admin and T-direct as similar as possible.

23 We do not further differentiate the urns by period and/or by the rank of the transfer recipient since those two factors are empirically irrelevant (and have no implications for the wording of the instructions). Moreover, note that we do not inform participants of T-admin about the exact procedure that generates the transfers since that information could potentially convey a social norm.

24 Consequently, participants could earn more in longer sessions than in shorter sessions but (a) they also had higher opportunity costs of staying longer in the lab and (b) the difference between the shortest and the longest session was only about 5 min.

25 We thank an anonymous referee for this observation.

26 Unless otherwise specified, all our statistical tests are guided by the following principles: (1) Since the random continuation rule varied the duration of each experimental session, we only report results from the first 50 (guaranteed) periods of the game. (2) In period 1, each individual is an independent observation. From period 2 on, each group is an independent observation. Per treatment, there are 96 subjects, i.e. 16 statistically independent groups. (3) For comparisons between treatments we report P-values of two-sided Mann-Whitney rank-sum tests over group means. (4) For comparisons of observed behavior with theoretical predictions, we report P-values of two-sided Wilcoxon signed-rank tests over group means. (5) For comparisons between different ranks of the same treatment, we report P-values of two-sided Wilcoxon signed-rank tests of matched pairs. Decisions are first averaged over 50 periods, by individual. The means of rank i and rank j are then matched by group. For each comparison of any two ranks, there are thus 16 matched-pairs per treatment.

27 Note that when averaging over all ranks (as in Fig. 3), 5.5 is the highest possible mean payoff. Subgroups of ranks can achieve mean payoffs above 5.5 (as in Panel B of Fig. 4).

28 Averaged over all 50 periods, in the no-T treatment a earns substantially more than f ( p < . 001 ); among the directly adjacent ranks, a earns more than b (p = .020), b more than c (p = .017), c more than d (p = .038), d more than e (p = .002), e more than f (p = .083)

29 For comparison, the bourgeois equilibrium (without transfers) and the mixed equilibrium generate Gini coefficients of .32 and 0 respectively.

30 The mean obedience of others that rank f experiences in her first 40 encounters is a proxy for f’s belief about others’ disposition to obey the recommendation of the correlation device in the last 10 encounters.

31 A simple OLS regression reveals a slope of 2.82 (p = .033) for no-T, 1.39 (p = .014) for T-direct, 1.03 (p = .045) for T-pool, and 1.92 ( p < . 001 ) for T-admin.

32 For comparisons between different ranks of the same treatment, we report P-values of two-sided Wilcoxon signed-rank tests of matched pairs. Decisions are first averaged over 50 periods, by individual. The means of rank i and rank j are then matched by group. For each comparison of any two ranks, there are thus 16 matched-pairs per treatment.

33 The treatment differences in players’ willingness to concede become even more pronounced in late periods of the game. In the last 10 periods of the game, rank f’s willingness to concede is 21 percentage points higher (p = .025) when transfers (with identical transfer volume, by design) are exogenously administered (T-admin) instead of freely chosen by their counterpart (T-direct). See Figure A4.

34 See Figures A5 and A7 for more details. All transfer figures reported in this section describe mean transfers from x i = 10 to x i = 1 players (and not from x i = 1 to x i = 10 players), which account for 3333 / 3417 = 97.5 % and 2391 / 2471 = 96.8 % of all tokens transfered in T-direct and T-pool, respectively.

35 Note that if transfer behavior were mainly driven by “last place aversion” (Kuziemko et al. Reference Kuziemko, Buell, Reich and Norton2014), we should in fact have observed the opposite: lower ranks in T-direct transferring (1) less than the upper ranks in T-direct, and (2) less than the bottom ranks in T-pool.

36 In contrast for instance to contributions in the extensively-studied public good game (Isaac et al. Reference Isaac, McCue and Plott1985), which are positive-sum by design.

37 Since, by design, all groups in T-admin drew transfers from the exact same distribution, in Fig. 7 there is virtually no variance of transfers between groups. And yet, there is substantial variance in the mean willingness to concede, ranging from about .4 to 1. This heterogeneity shows that even holding transfers constant, there are sizeable idiosyncratic differences between (groups of) individuals.

38 Intercept of .50 (p = .001) and slope of .10 (p = .081) for T-direct, and intercept of .41 (p = .001) and slope of .19 (p = .007) for T-pool.

39 The effect of transfers on conceding in T-admin (.135–.227) is insignificantly different from zero (p = .232). This also holds in the other specifications.

40 Figure A8 in the “Appendix” shows that groups with higher early transfers (of upper ranks) systematically display higher transfers (of upper ranks) throughout the game in T-direct and T-pool but not in T-admin.

41 See “Appendix A.4”, and Tables A2 and A3 for details on the individual characteristics.

42 In fact, there is even a weakly negative effect in specification (4a) but it disappears when adding controls (4b).

43 We thank an anonymous referee for this observation.

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

References

Acemoglu, D., Naidu, S., Restrepo, P., & Robinson, J. A. (2015). Democracy, redistribution, and inequality. In Handbook of income distribution (pp. 18851966). Elsevier.Google Scholar
Acemoglu, D, & Robinson, JA (2000). Why did the west extend the franchise? Democracy, inequality, and growth in historical perspective. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 115(4), 11671199. 10.1162/003355300555042CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adermon, A, Lindahl, M, & Waldenström, D (2018). Intergenerational wealth mobility and the role of inheritance: Evidence from multiple generations. The Economic Journal, 128(612), F482F513. 10.1111/ecoj.12535CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Agranov, M, & Palfrey, T (2015). Equilibrium tax rates and income redistribution: A laboratory study. Journal of Public Economics, 130, 4558. 10.1016/j.jpubeco.2015.08.008CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ahn, T, Balafoutas, L, Batsaikhan, M, Campos-Ortiz, F, Putterman, L, & Sutter, M (2016). Securing property rights: A dilemma experiment in Austria, Mexico, Mongolia, South Korea and the United States. Journal of Public Economics, 143, 115124. 10.1016/j.jpubeco.2016.08.015CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ahn, T, Loukas, B, Batsaikhan, M, Campos-Ortiz, F, Putterman, L, & Sutter, M (2018). Trust and communication in a property rights dilemma. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 149, 413433. 10.1016/j.jebo.2018.01.009CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alesina, A, & Angeletos, G-M (2005). Fairness and redistribution. The American Economic Review, 95(4), 960980. 10.1257/0002828054825655CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alesina, A., & Giuliano, P. (2011). Preferences for redistribution. In Handbook of social economics (Vol. 1, pp. 93131). Elsevier.Google Scholar
Alexander, RD (1987). The biology of moral systems, New Brunswick: Transaction Publisher.Google Scholar
Anbarcı, N, Feltovich, N, & Gürdal, M (2018). Payoff inequity reduces the effectiveness of correlated-equilibrium recommendations. European Economic Review, 108, 172190. 10.1016/j.euroecorev.2018.07.003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, D (1999). The aggregate burden of crime. The Journal of Law and Economics, 42(2), 611642. 10.1086/467436CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arifovic, J, & Ledyard, J (2018). Learning to alternate. Experimental Economics, 21(3), 692721. 10.1007/s10683-018-9568-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aumann, R (1974). Subjectivity and correlation in randomized strategies. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 1(1), 6796. 10.1016/0304-4068(74)90037-8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aumann, R (1987). Correlated equilibrium as an expression of Bayesian rationality. Econometrica, 55, 118. 10.2307/1911154CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baranski, A (2016). Voluntary contributions and collective redistribution. American Economic Journal: Microeconomics, 8(4), 149173.Google Scholar
Bardsley, N, Mehta, J, Starmer, C, & Sugden, R (2009). Explaining focal points: Cognitive hierarchy theory versus team reasoning. The Economic Journal, 120(543), 4079. 10.1111/j.1468-0297.2009.02304.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bartling, B, Weber, RA, & Yao, L (2014). Do markets erode social responsibility?. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 130(1), 219266. 10.1093/qje/qju031CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berg, J, Dickhaut, J, & McCabe, K (1995). Trust, reciprocity, and social history. Games and Economic Behavior, 10(1), 122142. 10.1006/game.1995.1027CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bhaskar, V (2000). Egalitarianism and efficiency in repeated symmetric games. Games and Economic Behavior, 32(2), 247262. 10.1006/game.2000.0810CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bigoni, M, Camera, G, & Casari, M (2019). Money is more than memory. Journal of Monetary Economics, 110, 99115. 10.1016/j.jmoneco.2019.01.002CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Binmore, K (1998). Game theory and the social contract: Just playing, Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Birdsall, N, Ross, D, & Sabot, R (1995). Inequality and growth reconsidered: Lessons from East Asia. The World Bank Economic Review, 9(3), 477508. 10.1093/wber/9.3.477CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bock, O, Baetge, I, & Nicklisch, A (2014). hroot: Hamburg registration and organization online tool. European Economic Review, 71, 117120. 10.1016/j.euroecorev.2014.07.003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bös, D, & Kolmar, M (2003). Anarchy, efficiency, and redistribution. Journal of Public Economics, 87(11), 24312457. 10.1016/S0047-2727(02)00048-8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowles, S, & Gintis, H (1995). Productivity-enhancing egalitarian policies. International Labour Review, 134, 559.Google Scholar
Bowles, S, & Gintis, H (2002). The inheritance of inequality. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 16(3), 330. 10.1257/089533002760278686CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, R, & Richerson, PJ (1989). The evolution of indirect reciprocity. Social Networks, 11(3), 213236. 10.1016/0378-8733(89)90003-8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Camera, G, & Casari, M (2009). Cooperation among strangers under the shadow of the future. The American Economic Review, 99(3), 9791005. 10.1257/aer.99.3.979CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carter, JR, & Anderton, CH (2001). An experimental test of a predator-prey model of appropriation. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 45(1), 8397. 10.1016/S0167-2681(00)00165-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Charness, G, & Rabin, M (2002). Understanding social preferences with simple tests. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 117(3), 817869. 10.1162/003355302760193904CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chetty, R, Hendren, N, Kline, P, & Saez, E (2014). Where is the land of opportunity? The geography of intergenerational mobility in the United States. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 129(4), 15531623. 10.1093/qje/qju022CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohn, A., Jessen, L., Klasnja, M., & Smeets, P. (2019). Why do the rich oppose redistribution? An experiment with america’s top 5%. mimeo.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crawford, V (1982). A theory of disagreement in bargaining. Econometrica, 50(3), 607 10.2307/1912604CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crawford, V, Gneezy, U, & Rottenstreich, Y (2008). The power of focal points is limited: Even minute payoff asymmetry may yield large coordination failures. The American Economic Review, 98, 14431458. 10.1257/aer.98.4.1443CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dal Bó, E, & Dal Bó, P (2011). Workers, warriors, and criminals: Social conflict in general equilibrium. Journal of the European Economic Association, 9(4), 646677. 10.1111/j.1542-4774.2011.01025.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dana, J, Weber, R, & Kuang, JX (2007). Exploiting moral wiggle room: Experiments demonstrating an illusory preference for fairness. Economic Theory, 33(1), 6780. 10.1007/s00199-006-0153-zCrossRefGoogle Scholar
DellaVigna, S (2009). Psychology and economics: Evidence from the field. Journal of Economic Literature, 47(2), 315–72 10.1257/jel.47.2.315CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Di Tella, R, Perez-Truglia, R, Babino, A, & Sigman, M (2015). Conveniently upset: Avoiding altruism by distorting beliefs about others’ altruism. The American Economic Review, 105(11), 34163442. 10.1257/aer.20141409CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Diermeier, D, Egorov, G, & Sonin, K (2017). Political economy of redistribution. Econometrica, 85(3), 851870. 10.3982/ECTA12132CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doerrenberg, P, Peichl, A, & Siegloch, S (2017). The elasticity of taxable income in the presence of deduction possibilities. Journal of Public Economics, 151, 4155. 10.1016/j.jpubeco.2015.10.001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duffy, J, & Kim, M (2005). Anarchy in the laboratory (and the role of the state). Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 56(3), 297329. 10.1016/j.jebo.2003.10.007CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duffy, J, Lai, E, & Lim, W (2017). Coordination via correlation: An experimental study. Economic Theory, 64, 265304. 10.1007/s00199-016-0998-8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dufwenberg, M, Gneezy, U, Güth, W, & Van Damme, E (2001). Direct vs indirect reciprocity: An experiment. Homo Oecon, 18, 1930.Google Scholar
Durante, R, Putterman, L, & van der Weele, J (2014). Preferences for redistribution and rerception of fairness: An experimental study. Journal of the European Economic Association, 12(4), 10591086. 10.1111/jeea.12082CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Durham, Y, Hirshleifer, J, & Smith, VL (1998). Do the rich get richer and the poor poorer? Experimental tests of a model of power. The American Economic Review, 88(4), 970983.Google Scholar
Eaton, BC, & White, WD (1991). The distribution of wealth and the efficiency of institutions. Economic Inquiry, 29(2), 336350. 10.1111/j.1465-7295.1991.tb01275.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elster, J (1992). Local justice: How institutions allocate scarce goods and necessary burdens, New York: Russell Sage Foundation.Google Scholar
Embrey, M, Frechette, G, & Lehrer, S (2015). Bargaining and reputation: An experiment on bargaining in the presence of behavioural types. The Review of Economic Studies, 82(2), 608631. 10.1093/restud/rdu029CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Engelmann, D., & Ortmann, A. (2002). The robustness of laboratory gift exchange: A reconsideration. Center for Economic Research and Graduate Education of Charles University, Economics Institute of the Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic Working Paper, Prague.Google Scholar
Epper, T., Fehr, E., & Senn, J. (2020). Other-regarding preferences and redistributive politics. Mimeo.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Esarey, J, Salmon, T, & Barrilleaux, C (2012). What motivates political preferences? Self-interest, ideology, and fairness in a laboratory democracy. Economic Inquiry, 50(3), 604624. 10.1111/j.1465-7295.2011.00394.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Falk, A, Fehr, E, & Fischbacher, U (2008). Testing theories of fairness—Intentions matter. Games and Economic Behavior, 62(1), 287303. 10.1016/j.geb.2007.06.001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fehr, E, Fischbacher, U, & Gächter, S (2002). Strong reciprocity, human cooperation, and the enforcement of social norms. Human Nature, 13(1), 125. 10.1007/s12110-002-1012-7CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fehr, E, & Gächter, S (2000). Fairness and retaliation: The economics of reciprocity. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 14(3), 159181. 10.1257/jep.14.3.159CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fehr, E, Kirchsteiger, G, & Riedl, A (1998). Gift exchange and reciprocity in competitive experimental markets. European Economic Review, 42(1), 134. 10.1016/S0014-2921(96)00051-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fehr, E, & Schmidt, K (1999). A theory of fairness, competition, and cooperation. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 114(3), 817868. 10.1162/003355399556151CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fetzer, T, & Marden, S (2017). Take what you can: Property rights, contestability and conflict. The Economic Journal, 127(601), 757783. 10.1111/ecoj.12487CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fischbacher, U (2007). z-Tree: Zurich toolbox for ready-made economic experiments. Experimental Economics, 10(2), 171178. 10.1007/s10683-006-9159-4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fong, C (2001). Social preferences, self-interest, and the demand for redistribution. Journal of Public Economics, 82(2), 225246. 10.1016/S0047-2727(00)00141-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gächter, S, & Falk, A (2002). Reputation and reciprocity: Consequences for the labour relation. Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 104(1), 126. 10.1111/1467-9442.00269CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gintis, H (2000). Strong reciprocity and human sociality. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 206(2), 169179. 10.1006/jtbi.2000.2111CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gintis, H (2007). The evolution of private property. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 64(1), 116. 10.1016/j.jebo.2006.02.002CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glaeser, E, Scheinkman, J, & Shleifer, A (2003). The injustice of inequality. Journal of Monetary Economics, 50(1), 199222. 10.1016/S0304-3932(02)00204-0CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greiner, B, & Levati, V (2005). Indirect reciprocity in cyclical networks: An experimental study. Journal of Economic Psychology, 26(5), 711731. 10.1016/j.joep.2004.04.003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grossman, H (1994). Production, appropriation, and land reform. The American Economic Review, 84(3), 705712.Google Scholar
Grossman, H (1995). Robin hood and the redistribution of property income. European Journal of Political Economy, 11(3), 399410. 10.1016/0176-2680(94)00062-OCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grossman, H (2001). The creation of effective property rights. The American Economic Review, 91(2), 347352. 10.1257/aer.91.2.347CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grossman, H, & Kim, M (1995). Swords or plowshares? A theory of the security of claims to property. Journal of Political Economy, 103(6), 12751288. 10.1086/601453CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grossman, H. I., & Kim, M. (1996). Predation and production. The political economy of conflict and appropriation (pp. 5771).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamman, J, Loewenstein, G, & Weber, R (2010). Self-interest through delegation: An additional rationale for the principal–agent relationship. The American Economic Review, 100(4), 1826–46 10.1257/aer.100.4.1826CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hirshleifer, J (1991). The paradox of power. Economics and Politics, 3(3), 177200. 10.1111/j.1468-0343.1991.tb00046.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hirshleifer, J (1995). Anarchy and its breakdown. Journal of Political Economy, 103(1), 2652. 10.1086/261974CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hopkins, E, & Kornienko, T (2004). Running to keep in the same place: Consumer choice as a game of status. The American Economic Review, 94(4), 10851107. 10.1257/0002828042002705CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hopkins, E, & Kornienko, T (2009). Status, affluence, and inequality: Rank-based comparisons in games of status. Games and Economic Behavior, 67(2), 552568. 10.1016/j.geb.2009.02.004CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Isaac, M, McCue, K, & Plott, C (1985). Public goods provision in an experimental environment. Journal of Public Economics, 26(1), 5174. 10.1016/0047-2727(85)90038-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Isoni, A, Poulsen, A, Sugden, R, & Tsutsui, K (2013). Focal points in tacit bargaining problems: Experimental evidence. European Economic Review, 59, 167188. 10.1016/j.euroecorev.2012.12.005CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahlenberg, R (2010). Affirmative action for the rich: Legacy preferences in college admissions, New York: Century Foundation Press.Google Scholar
Kuziemko, I, Buell, R, Reich, T, & Norton, M (2014). Last-place aversion: Evidence and redistributive implications. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 129(1), 105149. 10.1093/qje/qjt035CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lipsey, R, & Lancaster, K (1956). The general theory of second best. The Review of Economic Studies, 24(1), 1132. 10.2307/2296233CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCabe, KA, Rassenti, SJ, & Smith, VL (1996). Game theory and reciprocity in some extensive form experimental games. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 93(23), 1342113428. 10.1073/pnas.93.23.13421CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mehta, J, Starmer, C, & Sugden, R (1994). The nature of salience: An experimental investigation of pure coordination games. The American Economic Review, 84(3), 658673.Google Scholar
Merlo, A (2003). Income distribution, police expenditures, and crime: A political economy perspective. Journal of the European Economic Association, 1(2–3), 450458. 10.1162/154247603322391080CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Midgley, J (1999). Growth, redistribution, and welfare: Toward social investment. Social Service Review, 73(1), 321. 10.1086/515795CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moulin, H (2004). Fair division and collective welfare, Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Myerson, R (1994). Communication, correlated equilibria and incentive compatibility. Handbook of Game Theory with Economic Applications, 2, 827847. 10.1016/S1574-0005(05)80056-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nowak, M, & Sigmund, K (2005). Evolution of indirect reciprocity. Nature, 437(7063), 12911298. 10.1038/nature04131CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Putterman, L, Roemer, JE, & Silvestre, J (1998). Does egalitarianism have a future?. Journal of Economic Literature, 36(2), 861902.Google Scholar
Rapoport, A, Guyer, M, & Gordon, D (1976). The 2x2 game, Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Rosenthal, R (1989). A bounded-rationality approach to the study of noncooperative games. International Journal of Game Theory, 18(3), 273292. 10.1007/BF01254292CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roth, A, & Murnighan, K (1978). Equilibrium behavior and repeated play of the prisoner’s dilemma. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 17(2), 189198. 10.1016/0022-2496(78)90030-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ryvkin, D, & Semykina, A (2017). An experimental study of democracy breakdown, income and inequality. Experimental Economics, 20(2), 420447. 10.1007/s10683-016-9490-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saez, E, Slemrod, J, & Giertz, S (2012). The elasticity of taxable income with respect to marginal tax rates: A critical review. Journal of Economic Literature, 50(1), 350. 10.1257/jel.50.1.3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sausgruber, R, & Tyran, J-R (2011). Are we taxing ourselves?. Journal of Public Economics, 95(1–2), 164176. 10.1016/j.jpubeco.2010.10.002CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schelling, T (1956). An essay on bargaining. The American Economic Review, 46(3), 281306.Google Scholar
Schelling, T (1960). The strategy of conflict, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Schotter, A, & Sopher, B (2003). Social learning and coordination conventions in intergenerational games: An experimental study. Journal of Political Economy, 111(3), 498529. 10.1086/374187CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Selten, R (1975). Reexamination of the perfectness concept for equilibrium points in extensive games. International Journal of Game Theory, 4(1), 2555. 10.1007/BF01766400CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skaperdas, S (1992). Cooperation, conflict, and power in the absence of property rights. The American Economic Review, 82, 720739.Google Scholar
Sonsino, D, & Sirota, J (2003). Strategic pattern recognition—experimental evidence. Games and Economic Behavior, 44(2), 390411. 10.1016/S0899-8256(03)00040-XCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trabandt, M, & Uhlig, H (2011). The Laffer curve revisited. Journal of Monetary Economics, 58(4), 305327. 10.1016/j.jmoneco.2011.07.003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Fig. 1 Stage game

Figure 1

Fig. 2 Equilibrium payoffs by rank. The dashed horizontal line slightly below l denotes expected payoffs in the mixed equilibrium. The solid diagonal line shows expected payoffs in the bourgeois equilibrium without transfers, ranging from an expected payoff of h for rank 1 to an expected payoff of l for rank N. The shaded area up to the solid horizontal line at h+l2 shows the bourgeois equilibrium with varying volume of transfers

Figure 2

Fig. 3 Payoffs over time. Mean payoffs after transfers. The solid (dashed) horizontal line at 5.5 (.9) denotes predicted average payoffs in the bourgeois equilibrium (mixed equilibrium). The 95% confidence intervals capture the between-group variation around the treatment means

Figure 3

Fig. 4 Payoffs over time—lower vs. upper ranks. Mean payoffs after transfers, for A ranks d-f, B ranks a-c. The solid (dashed) horizontal line at 5.5 (.9) denotes predicted average payoffs in the bourgeois equilibrium with maximum redistribution (mixed equilibrium). The 95% confidence intervals capture the between-group variation around the treatment means

Figure 4

Fig. 5 Effect of redistribution on payoff, by ranks. Mean payoffs before (left) and after (right) transfers, averaged over AB periods 1–50 or CD periods 41–50. The dashed horizontal line at .9 denotes expected payoffs in the mixed equilibrium. The solid diagonal line shows expected payoffs in the bourgeois equilibrium without transfers. The solid horizontal line at 5.5 shows the bourgeois equilibrium with maximum volume of transfers. The 95% confidence intervals capture the between-group variation around the treatment means

Figure 5

Fig. 6 Compliance with the status quo. Mean relative frequency of complying with the exogenous recommendation when one’s message is Aclaim (i.e. red field shown in bold) or Bconcede (i.e. blue field shown in bold). The solid (dashed) horizontal line denotes predicted behavior in the bourgeois equilibrium (mixed equilibrium). The 95% confidence intervals capture the between-group variation around the treatment means

Figure 6

Fig. 7 Transfers and conceding, by groups. Each dot depicts one group. There are 16 groups per treatment. Mean transfer given by the player earning xi=h, and P(a=concede|m=concede), the mean propensity of conceding when receiving the message concede (i.e. choose blue when blue field is shown in bold), averaged over all ranks. A For all 50 periods, and B for the last 10 periods of the game. The solid red (dashed blue) positive-slope line depicts the simple linear regression in T-direct (T-pool), with 95% confidence intervals. Regression line for T-admin not included because it is insignificantly different from zero (p = .666 and p = .554). The solid (dashed) black horizontal line denotes predicted behavior in the bourgeois equilibrium (mixed equilibrium)

Figure 7

Table 1 Willingness to concede and to transfer

Supplementary material: File

Chatziathanasiou et al. supplementary material

A Online-Appendix
Download Chatziathanasiou et al. supplementary material(File)
File 1.6 MB