Hostname: page-component-7b9c58cd5d-9klzr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-03-15T15:49:00.022Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

How common is the common-ratio effect?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2025

Pavlo Blavatskyy*
Affiliation:
Montpellier Business School, 2300 Avenue des Moulins, 34185 Montpellier Cedex 4, France
Valentyn Panchenko*
Affiliation:
School of Economics, UNSW Business School, UNSW, Sydney, NSW 2032, Australia
Andreas Ortmann*
Affiliation:
School of Economics, UNSW Business School, UNSW, Sydney, NSW 2032, Australia
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The common-ratio effect and the Allais Paradox (common-consequence effect) are the two best‐known violations of Expected Utility Theory. We reexamine data from 39 articles reporting experiments (143 designs/parameterizations, 14,909 observations) and find that the common-ratio effect is systematically affected by experimental design and implementation choices. The common-ratio effect is more likely to be observed in experiments with a low common-ratio factor, a high ratio of middle to highest outcome, when lotteries are presented as simple probability distributions (not in a compound/frequency form), and with high hypothetical incentives.

Type
Original Paper
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC-BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s) 2022

1 Introduction

Expected Utility Theory (EUT) is one of the oldest and widely used criteria for decision making under risk. Bernoulli (Reference Bernoulli1738) first proposed EUT to resolve the St. Petersburg Paradox. Von Neumann and Morgenstern (Reference von Neumann and Morgenstern1947) provided a normatively appealing axiomatization of EUT. Yet, Allais (Reference Allais1953) challenged the descriptive accuracy of EUT with two examples. His first example (Allais, Reference Allais1953, p. 527) is known as the Allais Paradox or common-consequence effect. Following MacCrimmon and Larsson (Reference MacCrimmon, Larsson, Allais and Hagen1979), his second example (Allais, Reference Allais1953, p. 529) is known as the common-ratio effect. One illustration of this effect, due to Kahneman and Tversky (Reference Kahneman and Tversky1979, p. 266), is that subjects choose $3,000 for sure over an 80% chance of winning $4,000 but choose a 20% chance of $4,000 over a 25% chance of $3,000 (when probabilities are scaled down by the same ratio, which gives the effect its name).

A wide-spread perception is that the common-ratio effect is a robust behavioral regularity. More than 40 years ago MacCrimmon and Larsson (Reference MacCrimmon, Larsson, Allais and Hagen1979, Sect. 5.3, p. 369) concluded that “even though the common-consequence problem … is generally called the ‘Allais Paradox’, the [common-ratio effect] which is also due to Allais is more of a ‘paradox’ (if either is) in the sense that it elicits a higher rate of violation of the [EUT] axioms.” Given that the effect has since been tested in numerous studies, we can verify its experimental robustness. Our methodology is similar in spirit to meta-studies: we re-analyze experimental data collected in previous studies (meta-studies re-analyze previously published statistics).

Blavatskyy et al. (Reference Blavatskyy, Ortmann and Panchenko2022) re-analyzed data from 29 articles (81 experimental designs/ parameterizations, 8,947 observations) on the Allais Paradox and found that the standard paradox was recorded in 38 designs (46.9%), no paradox was recorded in 27 designs (33.3%) and the reverse paradox was recorded in the remaining 16 designs (19.8%). Here we reexamine data from 39 articles with 143 experimental parameterizations of the common-ratio effect (14,909 observations). Out of these 143 designs, the standard common-ratio effect was found in 85 designs (59.4%), no common- ratio effect was found in 43 designs (30.1%), and the reverse common-ratio effect was found in the remaining 15 designs (10.5%).

Our econometric analysis shows that the common-ratio effect is susceptible to similar effects of experimental design, implementation, and parameter choices as the Allais Paradox. Specific choices of an experimenter can make the common-ratio effect appear, disappear, or reverse. It is important to raise awareness of such effects to promote the development of appropriate non-expected utility theories that can rationalize these effects.

The remainder of the paper is organized as follows. In Sect. 2, we briefly explain the common-ratio effect. In Sect. 3, we explain how we collected the data. In Sect. 4, we provide our regression analysis. In Sect. 5, we offer a concluding discussion.

2 The common-ratio effect

The original Allais (Reference Allais1953, p. 529) example of the common-ratio effect is the following: A decision maker can prefer ₣100 million for certain over 98% chance of ₣500 million (and a 2% chance of nothing) and, at the same time, she can prefer 0.98% chance of ₣500 million (and a 99.02% chance of nothing) over a 1% chance of ₣100 million (and 99% chance of nothing). In the second binary choice problem, the chances of positive gains are scaled down from the corresponding chances in the first binary choice problem by a common ratio of 1/100. This gives the effect its name.

The common-ratio effect is illustrated in the probability triangle (Machina, Reference Machina1982) in Fig. 1 (axes not to scale). Point A (0,0) represents the prospect of ₣100 million for certain. Point B (0.02, 0.98) represents a 98% chance of ₣500 million. Point C (0.99,0) represents a 1% chance of ₣100 million. Point D (0.9902, 0.0098) represents a 0.98% chance of ₣500 million. Due to the scaling by a common ratio, line AB is parallel to line CD. The left panel of Fig. 1 shows a typical family of indifference curves for an expected-utility maximizer—positively-sloped parallel straight lines. Since AB is parallel to CD, A is located on a higher indifference curve than B (as shown on the left panel of Fig. 1) if and only if C is located on a higher indifference curve than D. Thus, an expected-utility maximizer weakly prefers A over B if and only if she weakly prefers C over D (a risk-averse choice pattern consistent with EUT).

Fig. 1 Illustration of the common-ratio effect in the probability triangle (not to scale)

A choice of A over B and D over C violates EUT (except for a special case of indifference) and we refer to this choice pattern as the common-ratio pattern. The right panel of Fig. 1 illustrates the common-ratio choice pattern. A decision maker who chooses B over A and C over D likewise violates EUT and we call this the reverse common-ratio pattern. Typically, the majority of decision makers reveal the common-ratio choice pattern and only a minority reveal the reverse common-ratio pattern. It is these behavioural regularities that became known as the common-ratio effect.

Several design, implementation, and parameter choices could affect the likelihood of observing the common-ratio effect. First, a small common ratio reduces the difference in expected utility between lotteries in the second binary choice (“scaled-down” lotteries C and D). Loomes (Reference Loomes2005, p. 305) argued that this may increase certain instances of the common-ratio effect when decision makers are prone to Fechner (Reference Fechner1860/1966)-type random errors. Such errors are more likely in the second binary choice between “scaled-down” lotteries C and D, which differ little in expected utility, compared to the first binary choice between “scaled-up” lotteries A and B, which differ considerably in expected utility.

Second, the slope of lines AB and CD in the probability triangle might influence the likelihood of the common-ratio effect. Note that the slope of lines AB and CD in the probability triangle is an increasing function of the probability of the highest outcome in risky lottery B in the first common-ratio question. Loomes and Sugden (Reference Loomes and Sugden1998) experimented with several different slopes and found that parameterizations with higher slopes generally reveal higher instances of the common-ratio effect. Parameterizations with higher slopes create a similarity (or inconsequentiality) of probabilities in the second common-ratio problem (the probability of a non-zero outcome in lottery D becomes relatively similar to that in lottery C). This similarity (or inconsequentiality) can catalyze the common-ratio effect. Blavatskyy et al. (2020) reanalyzed experimental data from 81 experiments reported in 29 studies of the Allais Paradox and found that a relatively low slope in the probability triangle is likely to reverse the Allais Paradox. We test if this conclusion also holds for the common-ratio effect.

Third, instances of the common-ratio effect may be affected by the sheer size of monetary outcomes. Lotteries with larger outcomes may induce more risk-averse choices. Ceteris paribus, this increases the likelihood of EUT-consistent risk-averse choice pattern A≿B and C≿D.

Fourth, Blavatskyy (Reference Blavatskyy2010, experiment 2, pp. 232–5) found that the common-ratio effect not only disappears but is reversed when the medium outcome is moved away from the highest outcome. A parameterization with a relatively high ratio of middle to highest outcome may increase cognitive load making both common-ratio questions a harder decision problem, which might lead to a higher rate of EUT violations. Blavatskyy et al. (2020) found that the Allais Paradox is more likely in experiments with the medium outcome being close to the highest outcome.

Fifth, instances of the common-ratio effect may be affected by the nature of the incentives used in experimental studies. Debate is ongoing about the effects of hypothetical and real incentives in experimental economics. On the one hand, Kahneman and Tversky (Reference Kahneman and Tversky1979, p. 265) argued in favor of hypothetical incentives in experiments on individual choice under risk. On the other hand, financial incentives are the default choice in most economics experiments and there are good reasons for it (e.g., Hertwig & Ortmann, Reference Hertwig and Ortmann2001; Ortmann, Reference Ortmann, Svorencik and Maas2016). Hertwig and Ortmann (Reference Hertwig and Ortmann2001) argue that the choice of hypothetical or real incentives ought to be evidence-based.

Sixth, Carlin (Reference Carlin1992) found that the common-ratio effect is less likely when choice alternatives are represented as compound lotteries or in a frequency format rather than as simple probability distributions. In their meta-study, Blavatskyy et al. (2020) found such an effect for the Allais Paradox. To summarize, we identify six design and implementation details and parameter choices that might drive the results of experimental studies on the common-ratio effect: 1) common ratio itself; 2) slope of lines AB and CD in the probability triangle; 3) size of payoffs; 4) ratio of the middle to the highest outcome; 5) whether incentives are hypothetical or real; and 6) presentation of choice alternatives.

3 Data

We searched in the Scopus database with a string ( TITLE-ABS-KEY ( "common ratio") AND TITLE-ABS-KEY ( "experiment")) excluding non-economic articles, theoretical articles, and experimental studies that collect no data on the common-ratio effect (e.g., Andreoni & Sprenger, Reference Andreoni and Sprenger2012; Kelsey & Schepanski, Reference Kelsey and Schepanski1991; Müller-Trede et al., Reference Müller-Trede, Sher and McKenzie2018). To this list, we added articles identified in the process of data collection for our previous study (Blavatskyy et al. 2020) when in effect the authors collected experimental data on the common-ratio effect (some papers refer to the common-ratio problem as the Allais paradox, e.g., van de Kuilen & Wakker, Reference van de Kuilen and Wakker2006; Herrmann et al., Reference Herrmann, Hübler, Menkhoff and Schmidt2017). We discarded several experimental studies with unconventional parameterizationsFootnote 1 as well as between-subject testsFootnote 2 of the common ratio. Raw experimental data of Kahneman and Tversky (Reference Kahneman and Tversky1979) are lost and we cannot infer the frequencies of four choice patterns revealed in their common-ratio experiment. Starmer and Sugden (Reference Starmer and Sugden1989b) use the same experimental data as Starmer and Sugden (Reference Starmer and Sugden1989a). Birnbaum et al. (Reference Birnbaum, Schmidt and Schneider2017) re-analyze data of Birnbaum and Schmidt (Reference Birnbaum and Schmidt2015). This results in a list of 24 articles. Going through the references in these articles we identified another eight studies that collect data on the common-ratio effect. After circulating the first draft of our working paper we received feedback about seven additional recent studies collecting data on the common-ratio effect. With this final addition, we obtained 39 articles (preceded by an asterisk in the list of references). Data collected from these 39 articles (143 design/parameterizations with 14,909 revealed-choice patterns) are presented in Table 1.

Table 1 Experimental data on the common-ratio effect

In the first column of Table 1 we list the different experimental designs/parameterizations. In column 2 we enumerate the number of corresponding participants. Columns 3–6 of Table 1 list how many subjects revealed the four possible choice patterns (risk-averse and risk-seeking EUT-consistent choice patterns, common-ratio and reverse common-ratio choice patterns). Conlisk (Reference Conlisk1989) developed a test statistic, known as Conlisk z-statistic, which takes values close to zero under the null-hypothesis of there being no EUT violations. Large positive values of the statistic indicate that common-ratio choice patterns outnumber reverse common-ratio choice patterns. Large negative values of the statistic indicate the opposite (reverse common-ratio choice patterns outnumber common-ratio choice patterns). Columns 7 and 8 of Table 1 list Conlisk z-statistic and its corresponding p-value for each of 143 design/parameterizations.

The remaining columns of Table 1 show the realizations of the six design and implementation characteristics identified in the previous section as potentially relevant for instances of the common-ratio effect. Column 9 lists the probability of the highest outcome in risky lottery (B) in the first question (which is an increasing function of the slope of lines AB and CD in the probability triangle). Column 10 lists the common-ratio factor. Column 11 lists the highest outcome and its currency. Column 12 lists the ratio of middle to highest outcome. Column 13 is a dummy variable that equals one (zero) if the researchers used real (hypothetical) incentives. Column 14 shows whether choice alternatives were presented as simple lotteries (1), in frequency form (0*), or as compound lotteries (0). The last column is a dummy variable equal to one if experimental subjects were students.

The sources from which we collected data reported in Table 1 are listed in Table 2 (for 39 experimental articles). We do not consider data from stages 2 and 3 in the experiment of Baillon et al. (Reference Baillon, Bleichrodt, Liu and Wakker2016), repetitions 2–4 in Birnbaum and Schmidt (Reference Birnbaum and Schmidt2015), stages 2 and 3 in the experiment of Bone et al. (Reference Bone, Hey and Suckling1999), repetition 2 in Loomes and Sugden (Reference Loomes and Sugden1998) and repetitions 2–3 in Schmidt and Neugebauer (Reference Schmidt and Neugebauer2007) to avoid any confounding with the learning effects. We do not consider household-decision making in Bateman and Munro (Reference Bateman and Munro2005) to focus only on individual choice. We do not consider the repeated-play condition in Barron and Erev (Reference Barron and Erev2003) or the 10-play and 100-play conditions in DeKay et al. (Reference DeKay, Schley, Miller, Erford, Sun, Karim and Lanyon2016) to focus only on single realization of lotteries. Buschena and Zilberman (Reference Buschena and Zilberman1999, p. 261) report that 39% of subjects reveal common-ratio choice pattern in questions 1 and 2 but their Table 4 (p. 270) implies that this percentage is at least 55%-8% = 47%. We assume a typo and the percentage of common-ratio choice patterns in their experiment is taken to be 49%.

Table 2 Sources of experimental data

Experimental study

Source of experimental data reported in Table 1

Agranov and Ortoleva (Reference Agranov and Ortoleva2017)

Data archive and online supplementary material accessed on https://www.journals.uchicago.edu/doi/suppl/10.1086/689774

Baillon et al. (Reference Baillon, Bleichrodt, Liu and Wakker2016)

Baillon et al., (Reference Baillon, Bleichrodt, Liu and Wakker2016, p.106, Tables 6–7) and P. Wakker’s website https://personal.eur.nl/wakker/data/16.2.group.indiv/links.htm

Barron and Erev (Reference Barron and Erev2003)

Barron and Erev (Reference Barron and Erev2003, p. 220, p. 225), Table S.3 in sup material (http://journal.sjdm.org/16/16527/supp.pdf

Bateman and Munro (Reference Bateman and Munro2005)

Bateman and Munro (Reference Bateman and Munro2005, p. C183, Table 1; p. C187, supplementary material) and email from A. Munro

Battalio et al. (Reference Battalio, Kagel and Jiranyakul1990)

Battalio et al., (Reference Battalio, Kagel and Jiranyakul1990, p. 27–28; p. 37, Table 5)

Baucells and Heukamp (Reference Baucells and Heukamp2010)

Baucells and Heukamp (Reference Baucells and Heukamp2010, p. 155, Table 5), email M. Baucells

Beattie and Loomes (Reference Beattie and Loomes1997)

Beattie and Loomes (Reference Beattie and Loomes1997, p. 160, Fig. 1; p. 163, Table 1; p. 164)

Birnbaum (Reference Birnbaum, Reips and Bosnjak2001)

Birnbaum (Reference Birnbaum, Reips and Bosnjak2001, p.36, Table 5) psych.fullerton.edu/mbirnbaum/archive.htm

Birnbaum and Schmidt (Reference Birnbaum and Schmidt2015)

Birnbaum and Schmidt (Reference Birnbaum and Schmidt2015, p. 147, Table 1), email U. Schmidt

Blavatskyy (Reference Blavatskyy2010)

Blavatskyy (Reference Blavatskyy2010, p. 222, Table 1; p. 225, Table 2; p. 234, Table 3; p. 235)

Blondel et al. (Reference Blondel, Lohéac and Rinaudo2007)

Blondel et al., (Reference Blondel, Lohéac and Rinaudo2007, p.651, Table 2; p.651–652) Sect. 4.3.1 of WP

Bone et al. (Reference Bone, Hey and Suckling1999)

Bone et al., (Reference Bone, Hey and Suckling1999, p. 67; p. 72, Table 3; p. 73, Table 4) and an Excel file emailed by J. Bone

Burke et al. (Reference Burke, Carter, Gominiak and Ohl1996)

Burke et al., (Reference Burke, Carter, Gominiak and Ohl1996, p. 620, Table 1; p. 630 Data supplementary material)

Buschena and Zilberman (Reference Buschena and Zilberman1999)

Buschena and Zilberman (Reference Buschena and Zilberman1999, p. 259; p. 261; p. 270, Table A.1)

Butler and Loomes (Reference Butler and Loomes2011)

Butler and Loomes (Reference Butler and Loomes2011, p.517, Fig. 3), Excel file emailed by D. Butler

Carlin (Reference Carlin1992)

Carlin (Reference Carlin1992, p. 226, Table 3; p. 232 supplementary material)

Chetty et al. (Reference Chetty, Hofmeyr, Kincaid and Monroe2020)

Chetty et al., (Reference Chetty, Hofmeyr, Kincaid and Monroe2020, Sect. 3), https://doi.org/10.1016/j.socec.2020.101520

Chew and Waller (Reference Chew and Waller1986)

Chew and Waller (Reference Chew and Waller1986, p. 65, Table 3; p. 62, Table 2)

Da Silva et al. (Reference Da Silva, Baldo and Matsushita2013)

Da Silva et al., (Reference Da Silva, Baldo and Matsushita2013, p. 561; p. 562, Table 2; p. 565, Table 5)

DeKay et al. (Reference DeKay, Schley, Miller, Erford, Sun, Karim and Lanyon2016)

DeKay et al., (Reference DeKay, Schley, Miller, Erford, Sun, Karim and Lanyon2016, p. 365, Table 1), Tables S.2–14 of supplemen-tary material (http://journal.sjdm.org/16/16527/supp.pdf)

Fatas et al. (Reference Fatas, Neugebauer and Tamborero2007)

Fatas et al., (Reference Fatas, Neugebauer and Tamborero2007, p. 174; 186–189; Table 2, p. 189)

Harless and Camerer (Reference Harless and Camerer1994)

Harless and Camerer (Reference Harless and Camerer1994, p. 1271; 1272, Table VII)

Harrison et al. (Reference Harrison, Hofmeyr, Ross and Swarthout2018)

Harrison et al., (Reference Harrison, Hofmeyr, Ross and Swarthout2018, p. 328–330) and https://cear.gsu.edu/gwh/

Herrmann et al. (Reference Herrmann, Hübler, Menkhoff and Schmidt2017)

Herrmann et al., (Reference Herrmann, Hübler, Menkhoff and Schmidt2017, pp. 132–133; p. 139, Table 2)

Hey and DiCagno (Reference Hey and DiCagno1990)

Hey and DiCagno (Reference Hey and DiCagno1990, pp. 286–287; pp. 288–289, Table 1; pp. 305–306, supplementary material)

Leland et al. (Reference Leland, Schneider and Wilcox2019)

Supplementary material SM3, an Excel file emailed by N. Wilcox

Linde and Vis (Reference Linde and Vis2017)

Linde and Vis (Reference Linde and Vis2017, p. 108, Table 1), DTA file emailed by B. Vis

Loomes (Reference Loomes1988)

Loomes (Reference Loomes1988, p.48, Table2; p.51–52; p. 53, Table 4)

Loomes and Sugden (Reference Loomes and Sugden1998)

Loomes and Sugden (Reference Loomes and Sugden1998, p. 587–588, Fig. 2; p. 589), Loomes et al., (Reference Loomes, Moffatt and Sugden2002, p. 111, Table 2a); p. 112, Table 2b)

Loomes and Sugden (Reference Loomes and Sugden1987)

Loomes and Sugden (Reference Loomes and Sugden1987, p.123; p.124, Fig. 2; p.125, Table 2)

MacCrimmon and Larsson (Reference MacCrimmon, Larsson, Allais and Hagen1979)

MacCrimmon and Larsson (Reference MacCrimmon, Larsson, Allais and Hagen1979, pp. 354–357)

Nebout and Dubois (Reference Nebout and Dubois2014)

Nebout and Dubois (Reference Nebout and Dubois2014, p. 25; p. 27; p. 30, Table 2)

Quattrone and Tversky (Reference Quattrone and Tversky1988)

Quattrone and Tversky (Reference Quattrone and Tversky1988, p. 721; p. 731–732)

Schmidt and Neugebauer (Reference Schmidt and Neugebauer2007)

Schmidt and Neugebauer (Reference Schmidt and Neugebauer2007, pp.471–472; p. 480, supplementary material) and an Excel file emailed by U. Schmidt

Schneider and Shor (Reference Schneider and Shor2017)

Schneider and Shor (Reference Schneider and Shor2017, p. 977; p. 980, Table 3)

Sopher and Gigliotti (Reference Sopher and Gigliotti1993)

Sopher and Gigliotti (Reference Sopher and Gigliotti1993, p. 87, Table II; p. 89–91; p. 102–103)

Starmer and Sugden (Reference Starmer and Sugden1989a)

Starmer and Sugden (Reference Starmer and Sugden1989a, p. 163–166; p. 171, Table 3)

van de Kuilen and Wakker (Reference van de Kuilen and Wakker2006)

van de Kuilen and Wakker (Reference van de Kuilen and Wakker2006, p. 159), data set downloaded from https://personal.eur.nl/wakker/data/data2006.1allaislearn.htm

Wu (Reference Wu1994)

Wu (Reference Wu1994, p. 42; p. 48, Table 3)

Figure 2 shows the fractions of the observed outcomes of choice patterns across all the experiments in the dataset depending on whether incentives are hypothetical or real, large or small, that is above or below the corresponding median payoff in 2010 USD.Footnote 3 The EUT-consistent risk-averse (AC) pattern is most prevalent in case of real large payoffs, whereas common-ratio (AD) pattern appears in the case of hypothetical large payoff. Interestingly, small hypothetical and real payoffs exhibit similar and closer to uniformly-distributed choice patterns.

Fig. 2 Frequency of choice patterns for each of four payoff categories—hypothetical payoffs, large and small, i.e., above and below the median hypothetical payoff of $123 (in 2010 USD) and real payoffs, large and small, relatively to the median real payoff of $34 (in 2010 USD)

4 Regression Analysis

In every experiment each subject can reveal only one of four possible choice patterns: risk-averse EUT-consistent choice, risk-seeking EUT-consistent choice, common-ratio choice pattern, and reverse common-ratio choice pattern. In this case, a multinomial logistic specification is appropriate:

ln P i P RA EUT = β i 0 + β i 1 ln P × I + β i 2 ln P × 1 - I + β i 3 I + β i 4 L + β i 5 S + β i 6 O + β i 7 PH + β i 8 CR ,

where P i is the probability of observing a specific choice pattern, i = {risk-seeking EUT, common-ratio, and reverse common-ratio} and risk-averse EUT-consistent choice pattern is set as the baseline outcome and explanatory variables are:

  • highest outcome P (column 11 of Table 1, after conversion to 2010 USD, see footnote 3);

  • real-incentives dummy variable I (column 13 of Table 1);

  • probability of the highest outcome in a risky lottery in the first common-ratio questionFootnote 4 PH (column 9 of Table 1); and

  • the ratio of middle to highest outcome O (column 12 of Table 1);

  • lottery presentation categorical variable L (column 14 of Table 1)Footnote 5;

  • student dummy variable S (column 15 of Table 1)Footnote 6;

  • the common ratio CR (column 10 of Table 1).

The highest outcomes P are natural-logged to reconcile a wide range of their values and to reflect saturation. There is a strong negative correlation between ln P and the real incentives dummy variable I , as studies with high payoffs use only hypothetical incentives. We use the interaction terms ln P × I and ln P × 1 - I to allow for different slopes for ln P for the cases of real and hypothetical payoffs, respectively. We also consider several alternative model specifications presented in Table 4 in the supplementary material. (They produce similar results with a lower goodness of fit.)

Table 3 presents the average marginal effects (observation-specific marginal effects averaged over all observations) of the 4-outcome logistic regression (regression coefficients β are presented in Table 5 in the supplementary material). Note that average marginal effects for each explanatory variable sum up to zero over the four possible choice patterns. Table 3 reports regular standard errors as well as cluster-robust standard errors. The cluster-robust method allows for correlated residuals within clusters, but not across clusters. Correlations may be induced by some unobserved conditions specific to a cluster. We cluster at the level of the country resulting in 11 clusters.

Table 3 Average marginal effects computed from the logit model

Prob. of choice

Explanatory variables

lnP × I

lnP × ( 1 - I )

I

PH

O

L

S

CR

(ln payoffs, real)

(ln payoffs, hypoth.)

(= 1, real incent.)

(prob. highest outcome)

(= mid/high outcome)

(= 1, simp. lottery)

(= 1, student)

(common ratio)

P(EUT risk-averse)

0.028

− 0.002

0.128

0.384

0.064

− 0.032

0.012

0.483

stand errors

(0.011)

(0.002)

(0.041)

(0.044)

(0.011)

(0.024)

(0.013)

(0.022)

p-values

0.009

0.338

0.002

0

0

0.178

0.36

0

Cl stand errors

(0.083)

(0.007)

(0.289)

(0.197)

(0.045)

(0.089)

(0.058)

(0.049)

Cl p-value

0.732

0.811

0.657

0.051

0.162

0.719

0.833

0

P(EUT risk-seeking)

0.043

0.004

0.125

0.337

0.028

0.153

0.022

0.076

stand errors

(0.008)

(0.001)

(0.032)

(0.037)

(0.009)

(0.017)

(0.011)

(0.018)

p-values

0

0.012

0

0

0.001

0

0.053

0

Cl stand errors

(0.038)

(0.007)

(0.152)

(0.078)

(0.026)

(0.049)

(0.035)

(0.077)

Cl p-values

0.254

0.618

0.412

0

0.278

0.002

0.531

0.321

P(common-ratio)

0.054

0.011

0.244

− 0.080

0.147

0.212

0.040

0.537

stand errors

(0.010)

(0.001)

(0.039)

(0.044)

(0.010)

(0.024)

(0.012)

(0.023)

p-values

0

0

0

0.068

0

0

0.001

0

Cl stand errors

(0.038)

(0.003)

(0.102)

(0.112)

(0.030)

(0.053)

(0.033)

(0.078)

Cl p-values

0.162

0

0.017

0.474

0

0

0.217

0

P(reverse CR)

0.018

0.006

0.009

0.128

0.055

− 0.026

0.006

0.131

stand errors

(0.007)

(0.001)

(0.025)

(0.031)

(0.007)

(0.015)

(0.009)

(0.014)

p-values

0.007

0

0.731

0

0

0.069

0.499

0

Cl stand errors

(0.022)

(0.003)

(0.092)

(0.090)

(0.020)

(0.034)

(0.025)

(0.045)

Cl p-values

0.41

0.096

0.925

0.156

0.006

0.432

0.807

0.004

We report regular standard errors (in parenthesis), and the cluster-robust standard errors (clustered at the country level). Coefficients significant at 0.05 level for both the regular and cluster-robust methods are highlighted with bold black font. Coefficients significant at 0.05 level for the regular, but not the cluster-robust method are highlighted with italics. (Same convention for Tables 4, 5 in the supplementary material.)

Looking at the probability of observing the common-ratio choice pattern (the section of Table 3 highlighted in boxed text), we find that it is influenced by the following factors. First, a lower common ratio (the last column of Table 3) increases the probability that subjects reveal the common-ratio choice pattern by 0.054 for each 0.1 decrease in the common ratio largely because it decreases the likelihood that subjects reveal the risk-averse EUT-consistent choice. For instance, if we reduce the overall median common ratio of 0.25 to 0.01, as in the original Allais (Reference Allais1953, p. 529) example, the probability of observing the common-ratio choice pattern increases by approximately 0.13. This confirms the well-known observation that experiments with low common ratios produce high instances of EUT violations. We could also speculate that this fact is probably well-known because it happens to be the strongest factor influencing the likelihood of the common-ratio effect.

Second, conducting an experiment with hypothetical incentives increases the chance of observing the common-ratio choice pattern by 0.011 for each relative increase in payoffs (the third column of Table 3). In combination with the intercept term shifter (the fourth column) that is actually lower for the hypothetical incentives than for the real incentives, we conclude that very high hypothetical incentives lead to the increased probability of the common-ratio choice pattern relatively to the low hypothetical incentives. Conversely, for real incentives, the chance of observing the common-ratio choice pattern is reduced by 0.054 for each relative increase in real payoffs. Hence, high real incentives lead to the reduced observations of the common-ratio choice pattern in comparison to low real incentives. This is largely due to the fact that high real incentives increase the likelihood of the EUT-consistent choices (both risk-averse and risk-seeking).

Third, subjects are more likely to reveal the common-ratio effect when choice alternatives are described as simple probability distributions (not in a compound or frequency form), cf. the seventh column of Table 3. Largely this happens because subjects are then less likely to reveal the risk-seeking EUT-consistent choice pattern. For example, changing the presentation format from compound to simple lotteries increases the probability of observing the common-ratio effect by 0.212.

Fourth, designing the common-ratio experiment with the middle outcome being close to the highest outcome (cf. the sixth column of Table 3) favours the instances of the common-ratio choice pattern at the expense of EUT consistent choices and the reverse common-ratio choice pattern. Blavatskyy et al. (2020, Table 2) report a similar effect for the Allais paradox.

Based on our findings we can construct a common-ratio index capturing the main features of the experimental design that favor the common ratio effectFootnote 7:

CRindex = - 0.054 ln P × I + 0.011 ln P × 1 - I + 0.244 I + 0.147 O + 0.212 L + 0.537 CR

Figure 3 plots this index against the share of subjects revealing the common-ratio choice pattern in each of the 143 experimental designs in our data set. The index has predictive abilities.

Fig. 3 Share of subjects revealing the common-ratio choice pattern vs. common-ratio index. N = 143 experimental designs. Linear trend is indicated by the dotted line and its equation is reported

5 Discussion

Over the last three decades researchers have produced large quantities of data on numerous behavioral regularities. It is important to take stock as experimental results are sometimes contradictory and one can fail to see the forest for the trees, possibly misdirecting theory efforts. In this paper we have reexamined experimental data on one specific behavioral regularity in choice under risk — the common-ratio effect. Our methodology is similar to meta-studies that sample previously published results in a systematic and replicable manner except that we re-analyze previously collected experimental data rather than previously published results.

We believe that our approach limits the publication bias and selective reporting that may be present in traditional meta-studies (cf. Kvarven et al., Reference Kvarven, Strømland and Johannesson2020). We re-analyze experimental data from articles published on a variety of topics, not necessarily focusing on the common-ratio effect. For example, Agranov and Ortoleva (Reference Agranov and Ortoleva2017) study a preference for deliberate randomization in stochastic choice; Baillon et al. (Reference Baillon, Bleichrodt, Liu and Wakker2016) and Bone et al. (Reference Bone, Hey and Suckling1999) compare group and individual decision making; Bateman and Munro (Reference Bateman and Munro2005) study decision making in households; Battalio et al. (Reference Battalio, Kagel and Jiranyakul1990) and Harless and Camerer (Reference Harless and Camerer1994) compare the goodness of fit of different non-EUT theories; Buschena and Zilberman (Reference Buschena and Zilberman1999) study the effects of similarity; Blondel et al. (Reference Blondel, Lohéac and Rinaudo2007) study preferences of drug addicts; Butler and Loomes (Reference Butler and Loomes2011) study imprecision of preferences under risk; Chetty et al. (Reference Chetty, Hofmeyr, Kincaid and Monroe2020) investigate the trust game; Harrison et al. (Reference Harrison, Hofmeyr, Ross and Swarthout2018) study smoking behavior; Fatas et al. (Reference Fatas, Neugebauer and Tamborero2007) and Linde and Vis (Reference Linde and Vis2017) study decision making of politicians; Hey and DiCagno (Reference Hey and DiCagno1990) elicit indifference curves in the probability triangle; Loomes and Sugden (Reference Loomes and Sugden1998) compare the goodness of fit of different models of probabilistic choice; Schmidt and Neugebauer (Reference Schmidt and Neugebauer2007) study the effect of random errors on risky choice; Wu (1994) studies ordinal independence of preferences. Given that the primary focus of these studies is not the common-ratio effect per se (which appears in their experimental treatments by serendipity) there is no ex ante reason to expect any publication bias or selective reporting with respect to the common-ratio effect in these studies.

Examining a large body of empirical evidence on the common-ratio effect during the last 40 years shows some remarkable regularities. Some of these regularities are well-known. For example, the fact that experimental designs with a small common ratio induce more instances of the common-ratio choice pattern is built into many descriptive decision theories such as rank-dependent utility (Quiggin, Reference Quiggin1981) or cumulative prospect theory (Tversky & Kahneman, Reference Tversky and Kahneman1992) that use inverse S-shaped probability weighting function to capture this effect. Other regularities we documented above are less known if not outright surprising.

For example, we find that the common-ratio effect is more likely to be observed when choice alternatives are presented as simple probability distributions, i.e. not described in frequency or compound-lottery format. We also find that common-ratio experiments with very high hypothetical incentives are more likely to document the common-ratio choice pattern. If we subscribe to the point of view that substantially high real incentives reduce the impact of random errors, noise, or imprecision in revealed preferences (Hertwig & Ortmann, Reference Hertwig and Ortmann2001), then our results suggest that the EUT risk-averse outcome is a behavioral regularity that is more likely to be observed once randomness and imprecision in revealed preferences are reduced.

Another less known finding is that common-ratio experiments with middle lottery outcome being close to the highest lottery outcome are more likely to document the common-ratio choice pattern. This effect is consistent with findings in Blavatskyy (Reference Blavatskyy2010, experiment 2, pp. 232–5) that the common-ratio effect gets reversed when the middle outcome is moved away from the highest outcome. Testing the common-ratio effect with lotteries that have the middle outcome close to the highest outcome induces similarity (Rubinstein, Reference Rubinstein1988) in the second pairwise choice between scaled-down lotteries C and D. This could induce a higher likelihood of observing the common-ratio choice pattern.

The standard common-ratio effect was found in 85 out of 143 (59.4%) experimental designs analyzed in this paper. This could be interpreted as a large effect revealing strong evidence against expected utility theory. We do not disagree with this interpretation of the data but reserve our judgement. Our results indicate several experimental design and implementation choices that could affect the likelihood of the common-ratio effect. If the existing literature largely used designs favoring the standard common-ratio effect, then it is hardly surprising that the experimental results are problematic for expected utility theory. Yet, had the literature largely used other designs identified in our paper, then the experimental results would have been different. This suggest that a systematic exploration of the whole parameter space would be desirable.

It is important to raise awareness of how different behavioral regularities are affected by the design and implementation characteristics and parameter choices of experimenters. For empirical work, our findings are important for the design of future experiments. For theoretical work, our findings provide guidelines for the development of generalized non-expected utility theories. A good descriptive decision theory should not aim at capturing one canonical version of the common-ratio effect. In the spirit of Erev et al. (Reference Erev, Ert, Plonsky, Cohen and Cohen2017), it should be flexible enough to rationalize instances of the common-ratio effect in some experimental designs/parameterizations but not others.

Funding

Open Access funding enabled and organized by CAUL and its Member Institutions.

Footnotes

Supplementary Information The online version contains supplementary material available at https://doi.org/10.1007/s10683-022-09761-y.

This project was approved by the UNSW HREAP Executive under HC No 200085. The replication material for the study is available at https://doi.org/10.3886/E169821V1. We are grateful to Manel Baucells, Michael Birnbaum, John Bone, David Butler, Glenn Harrison, John Hey, Andre Hofmeyr, Alister Munro, Ulrich Schmidt and Barbara Vis for helpful comments and sharing their experimental data. We are indebted to editors Roberto Weber and Marie Claire Villeval as well as two anonymous referees for their constructive comments.

Pavlo Blavatskyy is a member of the Entrepreneurship and Innovation Chair, which is part of LabEx Entrepreneurship (University of Montpellier, France) and funded by the French government (Labex Entreprendre, ANR-10-Labex-11-01).

1 E.g. Ballinger and Wilcox (Reference Ballinger and Wilcox1997), lottery pair CRE2 in Birnbaum and Schmidt (Reference Birnbaum and Schmidt2015), A$40-group in Butler and Loomes (Reference Butler and Loomes2011), questions 9 and 10 in Da Silva et al. (Reference Da Silva, Baldo and Matsushita2013), Harrison (Reference Harrison1994, p. 244–245), Internet study E in Birnbourm (2001), experiments 2 and 3 in Loomes (Reference Loomes1988), common ratio tasks 1–8 in Rockenbach et al. (Reference Rockenbach, Sadrieh and Mathauschek2007), common ratio questions 8–9, 11–12, 17–18 and 24–25 in Schmidt and Neugebauer (Reference Schmidt and Neugebauer2007), common ratio lottery pairs in Selten et al. (Reference Selten, Sadrieh and Abbink1999), question pairs 2–3, 2–5 and 3–6 in Starmer and Sugden (Reference Starmer and Sugden1989a), and problem C3A-C3B in Wu (Reference Wu1994) that do not use a question with one riskless option; triple 4 in Bone et al. (Reference Bone, Hey and Suckling1999), context 2a in experiment 2 of Chew and Waller (Reference Chew and Waller1986), Harrison and Ng (Reference Harrison and Ng2016), Harrison and Swarthout (Reference Harrison and Swarthout2014) and questions 10–11 in Hey and DiCagno (Reference Hey and DiCagno1990) with the lowest lottery outcome being non-zero; experiment 1 in Chapman and Weber (Reference Chapman and Weber2006) that elicits certainty equivalents of two common-ratio lotteries; questions 7 and 8 in Da Silva et al. (Reference Da Silva, Baldo and Matsushita2013) and experiment of Berns et al. (Reference Berns, Capra, Moore and Noussair2007) with non-monetary outcomes; Harless (Reference Harless1992) and off-border treatment of experiment II in Sopher and Gigliotti (Reference Sopher and Gigliotti1993) with all lotteries located inside the probability triangle; Kagel et al. (Reference Kagel, Battalio and MacDonald1990), context 1b and 1c in experiment 1, context 2c in experiment 2 of Chew and Waller (Reference Chew and Waller1986), and stage 2 in Starmer and Sugden (Reference Starmer and Sugden1989a) with at least one negative outcome; MacDonald and Wall (Reference MacDonald and Wall1989) with all outcomes being losses; pricing and happiness rating of four common ratio lotteries in Schneider & Shor (Reference Schneider and Shor2017).

2 E.g. group REAL in Beattie and Loomes (Reference Beattie and Loomes1997), experiments CR5 and CR6 in Cubitt et al. (Reference Cubitt, Starmer and Sugden2001), Cubitt et al. (Reference Cubitt, Starmer and Sugden1998), study 2 in DeKay et al. (Reference DeKay, Schley, Miller, Erford, Sun, Karim and Lanyon2016), Hagen (Reference Hagen, Allais and Hagen1979), Keren and Wagenaar (Reference Keren and Wagenaar1987), Schmidt and Seidl (Reference Schmidt and Seidl2014) and Weber and Chapman (Reference Weber and Chapman2005).

3 We first apply the PPP conversion factor to all payoffs in foreign currencies to convert them to comparable USD payoffs and then use US CPI index with 2010 as a base year to bring all amount to 2010 USD. The PPP conversion factor and the US CPI index were sourced from the World Bank Database.

4 This is an increasing function of the slope of lines AB and CD in the probability triangle shown in Fig. 1.

5 Harless and Camerer (Reference Harless and Camerer1994) do not explicitly state their lottery representation format. They collect additional data points for the Chew and Waller (Reference Chew and Waller1986) experiment, who used a simple lottery representation. Therefore, we assume that Harless and Camerer (Reference Harless and Camerer1994) used a simple lottery representation.

6 MacCrimmon and Larsson (Reference MacCrimmon, Larsson, Allais and Hagen1979) do not specify their subject pool, we assume that they recruited students.

7 We thank a referee for this journal for the suggestion.

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

References

Agranov, M., & Ortoleva, P. (2017). Stochastic choice and preferences for randomization. Journal of Political Economy, 125(1), 4068.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allais, M. (1953). Le Comportement de l’Homme Rationnel devant le Risque: Critique des Postulates et Axiomes de l’Ecole Américaine. Econometrica, 21, 503546. 10.2307/1907921CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Andreoni, J., & Sprenger, C. (2012). Risk preferences are not time preferences. American Economic Review, 102(7), 33573376. 10.1257/aer.102.7.3357CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baillon, A., Bleichrodt, H., Liu, N., & Wakker, P. (2016). Group decision rules and group rationality under risk. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 52(2), 99116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ballinger, P., & Wilcox, N. (1997). Decisions, error and heterogeneity. Economic Journal, 107, 10901105. 10.1111/j.1468-0297.1997.tb00009.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barron, G., & Erev, I. (2003). Small feedback-based decisions and their limited correspondence to description-based decisions. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 16, 215233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bateman, I., & Munro, A. (2005). An experiment on risky choice amongst households. Economic Journal, 115(502), C176–-C189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Battalio, R. C., Kagel, J. H., & Jiranyakul, K. (1990). Testing between alternative models of choice under uncertainty: Some initial results. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 3(1), 2550. 10.1007/BF00213259CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baucells, M., & Heukamp, F. H. (2010). Common ratio using delay. Theory and Decision, 68(1–2), 149158. 10.1007/s11238-008-9130-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beattie, J., & Loomes, G. (1997). The impact of incentives upon risky choice experiments. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 14, 149162. 10.1023/A:1007721327452CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernoulli, D. (1738) “Specimen theoriae novae de mensura sortis”. Commentarii Academiae Scientiarum Imperialis Petropolitanae.Google Scholar
Berns, G. S., Capra, C. M., Moore, S., & Noussair, C. (2007). A shocking experiment: New evidence on probability weighting and common ratio violations. Judgment and Decision Making, 2, 234242. 10.1017/S1930297500000565CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Birnbaum, M. H. Reips, U-D, & Bosnjak, M. (2001). A Web-based program of research on decision making. Dimensions of Internet Science, Lengerich: Pabst Science Publishers 2355.Google Scholar
Birnbaum, M. H., & Schmidt, U. (2015). The impact of learning by thought on violations of independence and coalescing. Decision Analysis, 12, 144152. 10.1287/deca.2015.0316CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Birnbaum, M. H., Schmidt, U., & Schneider, M. D. (2017). Testing independence conditions in the presence of errors and splitting effects. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 54(1), 6185. 10.1007/s11166-017-9251-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blavatskyy, P. R. (2010). Reverse common ratio effect. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 40(3), 219241. 10.1007/s11166-010-9093-xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blavatskyy, P. R., Ortmann, A., & Panchenko, V. (2022). On the experimental robustness of the Allais paradox. American Economic Journal: Microeconomics, 14(1), 143146.Google Scholar
Blondel, S., Lohéac, Y., & Rinaudo, S. (2007). Rationality and drug use: An experimental approach. Journal of Health Economics, 26(3), 643658. 10.1016/j.jhealeco.2006.11.001CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bone, J., Hey, J., & Suckling, J. (1999). Are groups more (or less) consistent than individuals?. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 18(1), 6381. 10.1023/A:1007764411446CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burke, M. S., Carter, J. R., Gominiak, R. D., & Ohl, D. F. (1996). An experimental note on the Allais paradox and monetary incentives. Empirical Economics, 21, 617632. 10.1007/BF01180705CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buschena, D. E., & Zilberman, D. (1999). Testing the effects of similarity on risky choice: Implications for violations of expected utility. Theory and Decision, 46(3), 253276. 10.1023/A:1005066504527CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Butler, D., & Loomes, G. (2011). Imprecision as an account of violations of independence and betweenness. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 80(3), 511522. 10.1016/j.jebo.2011.05.008CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carlin, P. S. (1992). Violations of the reduction and independence axioms in Allais-type and common-ratio effect experiments. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 19(2), 213235. 10.1016/0167-2681(92)90091-OCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chapman, G. B., & Weber, B. J. (2006). Decision biases in intertemporal choice and choice under uncertainty: Testing a common account. Memory and Cognition, 34(3), 589602. 10.3758/BF03193582CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Chetty, R., Hofmeyr, A., Kincaid, H., & Monroe, B. (2020). The trust game does not (only) measure trust: The risk-trust confound revisited. Journal of Behavioral and Experimental Economics (forthcoming).Google Scholar
Chew, H. S., & Waller, W. S. (1986). Empirical tests of weighted utility theory. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 30(1), 5572. 10.1016/0022-2496(86)90042-8Google Scholar
Conlisk, J. (1989). Three variants on the allais example. American Economic Review, 79(3), 392407.Google Scholar
Cubitt, R. P., Starmer, C., & Sugden, R. (1998). Dynamic choice and the common ratio effect: An experimental investigation. Economic Journal, 108(450), 13621380. 10.1111/1468-0297.00346CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cubitt, R. P., Starmer, C., & Sugden, R. (2001). Discovered preferences and the experimental evidence of violations of expected utility theory. Journal of Economic Methodology, 8(3), 385414. 10.1080/13501780110103748CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Da Silva, S., Baldo, D., & Matsushita, R. (2013). Biological correlates of the Allais Paradox. Applied Economics, 45(4–6), 555568. 10.1080/00036846.2011.607133CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DeKay, M., Schley, D., Miller, S., Erford, B., Sun, J., Karim, M., & Lanyon, M. (2016). The persistence of common-ratio effects in multiple-play decisions. Judgment and Decision Making, 11(4), 361379. 10.1017/S193029750000379XCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Erev, I., Ert, E., Plonsky, O., Cohen, D., & Cohen, O. (2017). From anomalies to forecasts: Toward a descriptive model of decisions under risk, under ambiguity, and from experience. Psychological Review, 124(4), 369409. 10.1037/rev0000062CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fatas, E., Neugebauer, T., & Tamborero, P. (2007). How politicians make decisions: A political choice experiment. Journal of Economics, 92(2), 167196. 10.1007/s00712-007-0264-4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fechner, G. (1860/1966) Elements of Psychophysics. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.Google Scholar
Hagen, O. Allais, M., & Hagen, O. (1979). Towards a positive theory of preferences under risk. Expected utility hypotheses and the Allais Paradox, Springer 271302. 10.1007/978-94-015-7629-1_13CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harless, D. W., & Camerer, C. F. (1994). The predictive utility of generalized expected utility theories. Econometrica: Journal of the Econometric Society, pp. 12511289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harless, D. W. (1992). Predictions about indifference curves inside the unit triangle: A test of variants of expected utility theory. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 18, 391414. 10.1016/0167-2681(92)90017-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harrison, G. W. (1994). Expected utility and the experimentalists. Empirical Economics, 19, 223253. 10.1007/BF01175873CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harrison, G. W., Hofmeyr, A., Ross, D., & Swarthout, J. T. (2018). Risk preferences, time preferences, and smoking behavior. Southern Economic Journal, 85(2), 313348. 10.1002/soej.12275CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harrison, G. W., & Ng, J. M. (2016). Evaluating the expected welfare gain from insurance. The Journal of Risk and Insurance, 83(1), 91120. 10.1111/jori.12142CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harrison, G. W., & Swarthout, J. T. (2014). Experimental payment protocols and the Bipolar Behaviorist. Theory and Decision, 77, 423438. 10.1007/s11238-014-9447-yCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herrmann, T., Hübler, O., Menkhoff, L., & Schmidt, U. (2017). Allais for the poor: Relations to ability, information processing, and risk attitudes. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 54(2), 129156. 10.1007/s11166-017-9258-yCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hertwig, R., & Ortmann, A. (2001). Experimental practices in economics: A methodological challenge for psychologists?. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24(3), 383451. 10.1017/S0140525X01004149CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hey, J., & DiCagno, D. (1990). Circles and Triangles: An experimental estimation of Indifference lines in the Marschak-Machina triangle. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 3, 279306. 10.1002/bdm.3960030405CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kagel, J., Battalio, R. C., & MacDonald, D. (1990). Tests of 'Fanning Out' of indifference curves: results from animal and human experiments. American Economic Review, 80(4), 912921.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263291. 10.2307/1914185CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelsey, D., & Schepanski, A. (1991). Regret and disappointment in taxpayer reporting decisions: An experimental study. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 4(1), 3353. 10.1002/bdm.3960040104CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keren, G., & Wagenaar, W. A. (1987). Violation of expected utility theory in unique and repeated gambles. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning Memory, and Cognition, 13, 387391.Google Scholar
Kvarven, A., Strømland, E., & Johannesson, M. (2020). Comparing meta-analyses and preregistered multiple-laboratory replication projects. Nature Human Behavior, 4, 423434. 10.1038/s41562-019-0787-zCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Leland, J. W., Schneider, M., & Wilcox, N. T. (2019). Minimal frames and transparent frames for risk, time, and uncertainty. Management Science, 65, 39494450. 10.1287/mnsc.2018.3167CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Linde, J., & Vis, B. (2017). Do politicians take risks like the rest of us? An experimental test of prospect theory under MPs. Political Psychology, 38(1), 101117. 10.1111/pops.12335CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loomes, G., & Sugden, R. (1987). Testing for regret and disappointment in choice under uncertainty. Economic Journal, 97, 118129. 10.2307/3038234CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loomes, G. (1988). Further evidence of the impact of regret and disappointment in choice under uncertainty. Economica, 55(217), 4762. 10.2307/2554246CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loomes, G. (2005). Modelling the stochastic component of behaviour in experiments: Some issues for the interpretation of data. Experimental Economics, 8, 301323. 10.1007/s10683-005-5372-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loomes, G., Moffatt, P. G., & Sugden, R. (2002). A Microeconometric test of alternative stochastic theories of risky choice. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 24(2), 103130. 10.1023/A:1014094209265CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loomes, G., & Sugden, R. (1998). Testing different stochastic specifications of risky choice. Economica, 65, 581598. 10.1111/1468-0335.00147CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacCrimmon, K., Larsson, S. Allais, M., & Hagen, O. (1979). Utility theory: axioms versus paradoxes. Expected utility hypotheses and the Allais Paradox, Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
MacDonald, D. N., & Wall, J. L. (1989). An experimental study of the Allais Paradox over losses: some preliminary evidence. Quarterly Journal of Business and Economics, 28(4), 4360.Google Scholar
Machina, M. (1982). Expected utility’ analysis without the independence axiom. Econometrica, 50, 277323. 10.2307/1912631CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Müller-Trede, J., Sher, S., & McKenzie, C. R. (2018). When payoffs look like probabilities: Separating form and content in risky choice. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 147(5), 662670. 10.1037/xge0000415CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nebout, A., & Dubois, D. (2014). When Allais meets Ulysses: Dynamic axioms and the common ratio effect. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 48(1), 1949. 10.1007/s11166-014-9184-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ortmann, A. Svorencik, A., & Maas, H. (2016). Episodes from the early history of experimentation in economics. Witness seminar on the emergence of a field, Springer 195217. 10.1007/978-3-319-20952-4_9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quattrone, G. A., & Tversky, A. (1988). Contrasting rational and psychological analysis of political choice. American Political Science Review, 82(3), 719736. 10.2307/1962487CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quiggin, J. (1981). Risk perception and risk aversion among Australian farmers. Australian Journal of Agricultural Resource Economics, 25(2), 160169. 10.1111/j.1467-8489.1981.tb00393.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rockenbach, B., Sadrieh, A., & Mathauschek, B. (2007). Teams take the better risks. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 63, 412422. 10.1016/j.jebo.2005.04.023CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rubinstein, A. (1988). Similarity and decision-making under risk. Journal of Economic Theory, 46, 145153. 10.1016/0022-0531(88)90154-8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schmidt, U., & Neugebauer, T. (2007). Testing expected utility in the presence of errors. Economic Journal, 117, 470485. 10.1111/j.1468-0297.2007.02026.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schmidt, U., & Seidl, C. (2014). Reconsidering the common ratio effect: The roles of compound independence, reduction, and coalescing. Theory and Decision, 77(3), 323339. 10.1007/s11238-014-9456-xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schneider, M., & Shor, M. (2017). The common ratio effect in choice, pricing, and happiness tasks. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 30(4), 976986. 10.1002/bdm.2017CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Selten, R., Sadrieh, A., & Abbink, K. (1999). Money does not induce risk neutral behavior, but binary lotteries do even worse. Theory and Decision, 46, 211249. 10.1023/A:1005038628305CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sopher, B., & Gigliotti, G. (1993). A test of generalized expected utility theory. Theory and Decision, 35(1), 75106. 10.1007/BF01075236CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Starmer, C. (2000). Developments in non-expected utility theory: The hunt for a descriptive theory of choice under risk. Journal of Economic Literature, 38(2), 332382. 10.1257/jel.38.2.332CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Starmer, C., & Sugden, R. (1989). “Probability and juxtaposition effects: An experimental investigation of the common ratio effect. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 2(2), 159178. 10.1007/BF00056135CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Starmer, C., & Sugden, R. (1989). Violations of the independence axiom in common ratio problems: An experimental test of some competing hypotheses. Annals of Operations Research, 19, 79102. 10.1007/BF02283515CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297323. 10.1007/BF00122574CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van de Kuilen, G., & Wakker, P. (2006). Learning in the Allais paradox. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 33, 155164. 10.1007/s11166-006-0390-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
von Neumann, J., & Morgenstern, O. (1947). Theory of Games and Economic Behavior, 2Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Weber, B. J., & Chapman, G. B. (2005). “The combined effects of risk and time on choice: Does uncertainty eliminate the immediacy effect? Does delay eliminate the certainty effect?. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 96(2), 104118. 10.1016/j.obhdp.2005.01.001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wu, G. (1994). An empirical test of ordinal independence. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 9(1), 3960. 10.1007/BF01073402CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Fig. 1 Illustration of the common-ratio effect in the probability triangle (not to scale)

Figure 1

Table 1 Experimental data on the common-ratio effect

Figure 2

Table 2 Sources of experimental data

Figure 3

Fig. 2 Frequency of choice patterns for each of four payoff categories—hypothetical payoffs, large and small, i.e., above and below the median hypothetical payoff of $123 (in 2010 USD) and real payoffs, large and small, relatively to the median real payoff of $34 (in 2010 USD)

Figure 4

Table 3 Average marginal effects computed from the logit model

Figure 5

Fig. 3 Share of subjects revealing the common-ratio choice pattern vs. common-ratio index. N = 143 experimental designs. Linear trend is indicated by the dotted line and its equation is reported

Supplementary material: File

Blavatskyy et al. supplementary material

Supplementary Online Appendix
Download Blavatskyy et al. supplementary material(File)
File 52.4 KB