No CrossRef data available.
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 18 January 2024
The concept of voluntariness permeates the ethics and politics of migration and is commonly used to distinguish refugees from migrants. Yet, neither the precise nature and conditions of voluntariness nor its ethical significance for migrant rights and state obligations has received enough attention. The articles in this collection move the debate forward by demonstrating the complex ethical judgments involved in delineating voluntary from forced migration and in drawing out its political and institutional implications. In addition to highlighting the interplay between the voluntary and nonvoluntary elements of migration over time and across different sites of the migration journey, they provide a nuanced account of the various conditions of voluntariness and they challenge common ideas about its normative political consequences.
1 United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization, United Nations Convention on Migrants’ Rights: International Convention on the Protection of the Rights of All Migrant Workers and Members of Their Families, July 1, 2003 (Paris: UNESCO, 2005), p. 25, unesdoc.unesco.org/ark:/48223/pf0000143557.
2 Suella Braverman, cited in Rajeev Syal, “Charity Challenges Home Secretary's Claims about ‘Economic Migrants,’” Guardian, October 1, 2023, www.theguardian.com/politics/2023/oct/02/charity-challenges-home-secretarys-claims-about-economic-migrants#:~:text=Suella%20Braverman's%20claim%20that%20most,if%20their%20claims%20were%20processed.
3 Suella Braverman, “Keynote Address by UK Home Secretary Suella Braverman: UK-US Security Priorities for the 21st Century” (American Enterprise Institute, Washington, D.C., September 26, 2023), www.aei.org/events/keynote-address-by-uk-home-secretary-suella-braverman-uk-us-security-priorities-for-the-21st-century-web/.
4 Bloemraad, Irene, Kymlicka, Will, Lamont, Michèle, and Hing, Leanne S. Son, “Membership without Social Citizenship? Deservingness & Redistribution as Grounds for Equality,” Dædalus 148, no. 3 (Summer 2019), pp. 73–104Google Scholar.
5 Carens, Joseph H., The Ethics of Immigration (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013), p. 10Google Scholar.
6 Miller, David, Strangers in Our Midst: The Political Philosophy of Immigration (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2016)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
7 Kymlicka, Will, Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995)Google Scholar.
8 Ottonelli, Valeria and Torresi, Tiziana, “When Is Migration Voluntary?,” International Migration Review 47, no. 4 (Winter 2013), pp. 783–813CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Ottonelli, Valeria and Torresi, Tiziana, The Right Not to Stay: Justice in Migration, the Liberal Democratic State, and the Case of Temporary Migration Projects (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2022)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
9 Ottonelli and Torresi, “When Is Migration Voluntary?”; and Ottonelli and Torresi, The Right Not to Stay.
10 Olsaretti, Serena, “Freedom, Force and Choice: Against the Rights-Based Definition of Voluntariness,” Journal of Political Philosophy 6, no.1 (March 1998), pp. 53–78, at p. 53CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
11 Bartram, David, “Forced Migration and ‘Rejected Alternatives’: A Conceptual Refinement,” Journal of Immigrant & Refugee Studies 13, no. 4 (2015), pp. 439–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
12 McAdam, Jane and Wood, Tamara, “The Concept of ‘International Protection’ in the Global Compacts on Refugees and Migration,” Interventions 23, no. 2 (2021), pp. 191–206CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
13 Hart, H. L. A., Punishment and Responsibility: Essays in the Philosophy of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1968)Google Scholar.
14 G. A. Cohen, “On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice,” Ethics 99, no. 4 (July 1989), pp. 906–44.
15 Hart, Punishment and Responsibility.
16 Elizabeth S. Anderson, “What Is the Point of Equality?,” Ethics 109, no. 2 (January 1999), pp. 287–337.
17 Kymlicka, Multicultural Citizenship.