Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-6bf8c574d5-zc66z Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-03-11T17:17:39.065Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Scientific Realism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 February 2025

Timothy D. Lyons
Affiliation:
Indiana University, Indianapolis

Summary

The scientific realism debate directly addresses the relation between human thought and the reality in which it finds itself. A core question: Can we justifiably believe that science accurately describes the reality that lies beneath the limits of human experience? Exploring this question, this Element begins at the most foundational level of scientific realism, the endeavor to justify belief in the existence of unobservables by way of abduction. Raising anti-realist challenges, some much discussed in the literature but also some generally overlooked, it works its way toward more refined variants of scientific realism. Because scientific realism is the default position of many scientific realists themselves often assuming it is the default position of scientists– the emphasis will be on the challenges. Those challenges will also motivate the variants of scientific realism traced. The Element concludes with a brief articulation of the author's own position, Socratic scientific realism.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781108588430
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 20 February 2025

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Boyd, R. (1973). Realism, underdetermination and the causal theory of evidence. Nous, 7, 112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, N. (1983). How the Laws of Physics Lie. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, N. (1999). The Dappled World. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Devitt, M. (2010). Putting Metaphysics First: Essays on Metaphysics and Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Devitt, M. (2013). Realism/anti-realism. In Curd, M. and Psillos, S., eds., 2nd ed., The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science. London: Routledge, pp. 256–67.Google Scholar
Duhem, P. (1906 [1954]). The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory. P. Wiener (trans.), Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, (1963). How to be a good empiricist: A plea for tolerance in matters epistemological. In Baumrin, B., ed., Philosophy of Science: The Delaware Seminar, Volume 2, New York: Interscience Press, pp. 339.Google Scholar
Fine, A. (1986). Unnatural attitudes: Realist and instrumentalist attachments to science. Mind, 95, 149–79.Google Scholar
Ghins, M. (2002). Putnam’s no-miracle argument: A critique. In Clarke, S. and Lyons, T. D., eds., Recent Themes in the Philosophy of Science: Scientific Realism and Commonsense. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 121–37.Google Scholar
Glymour, C. (1984). Explanation and realism. In Leplin, J., ed., Scientific Realism. Berkeley: California University Press, pp. 173–92.Google Scholar
Haufe, C. (2016). Testing structural realism. In Haufe, C., ed., Special Section, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 59.Google Scholar
Hesse, M. (1976). Truth and the growth of scientific knowledge. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 2, 261–80.Google Scholar
Horwich, P. (1991). On the nature and norms of theoretical commitment. Philosophy of Science, 58, 114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2014). Systematicity: The Nature of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Khalifa, K. (2010). Default privilege and bad lots: Underconsideration and explanatory inference. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 24, 91105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1993). The Advancement of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. (1974). Logic of discovery or psychology of research? In Schilpp, P. A., ed., The Philosophy of Karl Popper, The Library of Living Philosophers, Vol. 14, Book 2. La Salle: Open Court, pp. 798819.Google Scholar
Ladyman, J., Douven, I., Horsten, L., and van Fraassen, B. (1997). A defense of van Fraassen’s critique of abductive reasoning: Reply to psillos. The Philosophical Quarterly, 47, 305–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A., eds., Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 91195.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, I. (1974). Popper on demarcation and induction. In Schilpp, P. A., ed., The Philosophy of Karl Popper, The Library of Living Philosophers, Vol. 14, Book 1. La Salle: Open Court, pp. 241–73.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48, 1941.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1996). Beyond Positivism and Relativism: Theory, Method, and Evidence. Boulder: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (2004). The epistemic, the cognitive, and the social. In Machamer, P. and Wolters, G., eds., Science, Values, and Objectivity. Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press, pp. 1423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. and Leplin, J. (1991). Empirical Equivalence and Underdetermination. Journal of Philosophy, 88, 449–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leplin, J. (1987). Surrealism. Mind, 96, 519–24.Google Scholar
Leplin, J. (1997). A Novel Defense of Scientific Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levin, M. (1984). What kind of explanation is truth? In Leplin, J., ed., Scientific Realism. Berkeley: California University Press, pp. 124–39.Google Scholar
Lipton, P. (1993/2004). Inference to the Best Explanation. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lipton, P. (1994). Truth, existence, and the best explanation. In Derkson, A. A., ed., The Scientific Realism of Rom Harré. Tilburg: Tilburg University Press, pp. 89111.Google Scholar
Lyons, T. D. (2001). The Epistemological and Axiological Tenets of Scientific Realism, Ph.D. Thesis, University of Melbourne, Australia.Google Scholar
Lyons, T. D. (2002). Scientific realism and the pessimistic meta-modus tollens. In Clarke, S. and Lyons, T., eds., Recent Themes in the Philosophy of Science: Scientific Realism and Commonsense. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 6390.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lyons, T. D. (2003). Explaining the success of a scientific theory. Philosophy of Science, 70(5), 891901.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lyons, T. D. (2005). Toward a purely axiological scientific realism. Erkenntnis, 63, 167204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lyons, T. D. (2006a). Review Peter Lipton’s Inference to the Best Explanation. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57(1), 255–8.Google Scholar
Lyons, T. D. (2006b). Scientific realism and the Stratagema de Divide et Impera. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57(3), 537–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lyons, T. D. (2009). Non-competitor conditions in the scientific realism debate. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 23(1), 6584.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lyons, T. D. (2012). Axiological scientific realism and methodological prescription. In de Regt, H. W., ed., EPSA Philosophy of Science: Amsterdam 2009. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 187–97.Google Scholar
Lyons, T. D. (2014). The historically informed modus ponens against scientific realism: Articulation, critique, and restoration. International Studies in Philosophy of Science, 27(4), 369–92.Google Scholar
Lyons, T. D. (2016a). Scientific realism. In Humphries, P., ed., Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Science. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 564–84.Google Scholar
Lyons, T. D. (2016b). Structural realism versus deployment realism: A comparative evaluation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 59, 95105.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lyons, T. D. (2017). Selectivity, historical threats, and the non-epistemic tenets of scientific realism. Synthese, 194, 3203–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lyons, T. D. (2018). Four challenges to scientific realism and the Socratic alternative. Spontaneous Generations: A Journal for the History and Philosophy of Science, 9(1), 146–50.Google Scholar
Lyons, T. D. (2019). Systematicity theory meets Socratic scientific realism: The systematic quest for truth. Synthese, 196, 833–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lyons, T. D. and Vickers, P. (2021). Contemporary Scientific Realism: The Challenge from the History of Science. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maxwell, J. C. (1873). Treatise on Electricity and Magnetism, Vol. 2, London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Maxwell, J. C. (1890). Collected Scientific Papers of James Clarke Maxwell. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Maxwell, N. (1999). Has science established that the universe is comprehensible? Cogito, 13(2), 139–45.Google Scholar
McMullin, E. (1984). A case for scientific realism. In Leplin, J., ed., Scientific Realism. Berkeley: California University Press, pp. 840.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMullin, E. (1991). Comment: Selective anti-realism. Philosophical Studies, 61, 97108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, J. S. (1859 [1998]). On Liberty. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. (1867). A System of Logic. New York: Harper.Google Scholar
Mullis, K. B. (1993). Press release. NobelPrize.org. www.nobelprize.org/prizes/chemistry/1993/summary/.Google Scholar
Musgrave, A. (1985). Realism versus constructive empiricism. In Churchland, P. and Hooker, C., eds., Images of Science. Chicago: Chicago University Press, pp. 197221.Google Scholar
Musgrave, A. (1988). The ultimate argument. In Nola, R., ed., Relativism and Realism in Science. Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 229–52.Google Scholar
Musgrave, A. (2017). Strict empiricism versus explanation in science. In Agazzi, E., ed., Varieties of Scientific Realism: Objectivity and Truth in Science. Switzerland: Springer, pp. 7193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, D. E. (2016). Psychedelics. Pharmacological Reviews, 68(2), 264355.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Peirce, C. S. (1958). Collected Papers. Vol. 5. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Poincaré, H. (1902 [1907]). Science and Hypothesis. New York: The Walter Scott.Google Scholar
Popper, K. (1959). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Psillos, S. (2016). From the evidence of history to the history of evidence: Re-thinking the pessimistic X-duction. Presented Feb 19 2016 at The History of Science and Contemporary Scientific Realism Conference, Indiana University-Purdue University Indianapolis.Google Scholar
Psillos, S. (2018). Realism and theory change in science, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Google Scholar
Psillos, S. and Ruttkamp-Bloem, E. (2017). Scientific realism: quo vadis? Introduction: New thinking about scientific realism. Synthese, 194, 3187–201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. (1974). The corroboration of theories. In Schilpp, P. A., ed., The Library of Living Philosophers, Vol. XIV, The Philosophy of Karl Popper. LaSalle: Open Court, pp. 221–40.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1976). What is “realism?Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 76(1), 177–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reichenbach, H. (1930). Kausalität und Wahrscheinlichkeit Erkenntnis, 1, 158–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, W. (1984). Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, W. (1985). Empiricism: The key question. In Rescher, N., ed., The Heritage of Logical Positivisms, Lanham: University Press of America, pp. 121.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. (1962). Science, Perception and Reality. Atascadaro: Ridgeview.Google Scholar
Sklar, L. (1981). Do unborn hypotheses have rights? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 62, 1729.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. (1963). Philosophy and Scientific Realism. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. (1968). Between Science and Philosophy. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. (1979). Difficulties for realism in the philosophy of science. Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science VI, 104, 363–75.Google Scholar
Stanford, K. (2006a). Darwin’s pangenesis and the problem of unconceived alternatives. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57, 121–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stanford, K. (2006b). Exceeding Our Grasp. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, R. (1997). Simplicity as Evidence of Truth. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. (2001). Epistemic Justification. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thagard, P. (1992). Conceptual Revolutions. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tolstoy, L. (1893 [1905]). The non-acting. In Wiener, L., ed., The Complete Works of Count Tolstoy, Volume 23, Miscellaneous Letters and Essays, Translated from the Original Russian and edited by Leo Wiener. Boston: Dana Estes, pp. 4365.Google Scholar
Tolstoy, L (1895 [1903]). The non-acting. Essays & Letters, trans. A. Maud. London: Grant Richards, pp. 94122.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1980). The Scientific Image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1985). Empiricism in philosophy of science. In Churchland, P. and Hooker, C., eds., Images of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 245308.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and Symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (2007). From a view of science to a new empiricism. In Monton, B., ed., Images of Empiricism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 337–83.Google Scholar
Wray, K. B. (2018). Resisting Scientific Realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Worrall, J. (1989). Structural realism: The best of both worlds? In Papineau, D., ed., Philosophy of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 139–65.Google Scholar
Worrall, J. (2000). Pragmatic factors in theory-acceptance. In Newton-Smith, W. H., ed., A Companion to the Philosophy of Science. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 349–57.Google Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Scientific Realism
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Scientific Realism
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Scientific Realism
Available formats
×